JiscMail Logo
Email discussion lists for the UK Education and Research communities

Help for PHD-DESIGN Archives


PHD-DESIGN Archives

PHD-DESIGN Archives


PHD-DESIGN@JISCMAIL.AC.UK


View:

Message:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Topic:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Author:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

Font:

Proportional Font

LISTSERV Archives

LISTSERV Archives

PHD-DESIGN Home

PHD-DESIGN Home

PHD-DESIGN  September 2008

PHD-DESIGN September 2008

Options

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Log In

Log In

Get Password

Get Password

Subject:

Research Into, By, and For Design

From:

Ken Friedman <[log in to unmask]>

Reply-To:

Ken Friedman <[log in to unmask]>

Date:

Sun, 21 Sep 2008 16:54:33 +1000

Content-Type:

text/plain

Parts/Attachments:

Parts/Attachments

text/plain (410 lines)

Research Into, By, and For Design

[Long Post]



Friends,

Earlier in the thread on design as research, I mentioned that I would
return to consider Christopher Frayling’s three-part concept of research
into design, research by design, and research for design. It was
mentioned here, but there was little more than a brief passing comment.

This is a long post. Please feel free to delete if you are not
interested.


Frayling’s Research in Art and Design

Sir Christopher Frayling’s Research in Art and Design is perhaps the
most-cited and least read document in design research. In most fields,
I’d reserve that distinction for Thomas Kuhn’s Structure of
Scientific Revolutions or Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann’s Social
Construction of Reality. These also show up often in design research,
but there is a big difference. Each of these books now has millions of
copies in print, and both are widely read, quoted, and cited in addition
to the great load of citations by those who have never seen either
volume.

Christopher Frayling’s (1993) pamphlet, Research in Art and Design, is
different to the others in two chief respects. First, it is a small
proposal, and copies are hard to find. Second, nearly no one has read
it. As nearly as I can tell, over 95% of the citations, references, and
loose paraphrases to Frayling’s idea come from people who have not
themselves read Frayling. Since I am among the few who own a copy, and
one of the fewer still who seems to have read it, I am writing this post
to clarify some of the issues for those who don’t know what is involved
in the oft-cited idea of “research into design, research by design, and
research for design.” (Some of you will find this information familiar.
I have written on the subject elsewhere.)

The problems that come up in the pamphlet are serious, but they are not
new. I’ll start this thread by examing the larger context in which
Frayling’s concept occupies a niche.


Design Research as Grounded Theory

One of the deep problems in design research is the common failure to
engage in some form of grounded theory, developing theory out of
practice. Instead, designers often confuse practice with research.
Rather than developing theory from practice through articulation and
inductive inquiry, some designers simply argue that practice is research
and practice-based research is, in itself, a form of theory
construction. 

Many of the problems in design research arise from category confusions.
In recent years, designers have become acquainted with the term “tacit
knowledge” articulated by Michael Polanyi (1966) in The Tacit Dimension.
Proposing tacit knowledge as the primary foundation of design research
reflects a surface acquaintance with the term by people who have not
read Polanyi’s work. 

Tacit knowledge is an important knowledge category. All professional
practice – including the practice of research – rests on a rich stock of
tacit knowledge. This stock consists of behavioral patterns and embodied
practice embedded in personal action. Some aspects of tacit knowledge
also involve facts and information committed to long-term memory. This
includes ideas and information on which we draw without necessarily
realizing that we do so, and it includes ideas and information that we
can easily render explicit with a moment’s thought. It also includes
concepts, issues, ideas, and information that can only be rendered
explicit with deep reflection and serious work. 

In social life and professional work, tacit knowledge is also reflected
in the larger body of distributed knowledge embedded in social memory
and collective work practice. Our stock of tacit knowledge enables us to
practice. Putting tacit knowledge to use in theory construction requires
rendering tacit knowledge explicit through the process of knowledge
conversion (Friedman 2001: 44; Nonaka and Takeuchi 1995: 59-73).

Tacit knowledge is necessary for human action. Without tacit knowledge,
embodied and habitualaction would require explicit conceptualization and planning each time.
The limits on immediate attention and cognition means that it would be
impossible to store and act on enough knowledge for effective individual
practice in any art or science, let alone accumulate the knowledge on
which a field depends (Friedman 2001: 42-44; Friedman and Olaisen 1999:
16-22). All fields of practice rest, in part, on tacit knowledge. (See,
f.ex., Bourdieu 1977, 1990; Chaiklin and Lave 1993; Friedman 2001:
42-44).

To say that tacit knowledge is not research and that design theory is
not identical with the tacit knowledge of design practice does not
diminish the importance of tacit knowledge. It merely states that
mistaken arguments about tacit knowledge as design knowledge demonstrate
the confusion of the scholars who make such statements. The confusion
rests on a simple failing: the failure to read and understand Polanyi. 

The notion that tacit knowledge and design knowledge are identical as
sources of theory development is linked with the idea that practice is a
research method. Both rest on category confusions and both arguments are
generally supported by references to Polanyi and Schon – again by
authors who have not read the works they cite.

If there is any confusion on Polanyi’s views, there should not be. He
settles the matter at the beginning of another book, Personal Knowledge.
Where tacit knowledge is embodied and experiential knowledge, theory
requires more. “It seems to me,” he writes, “that we have sound reason
for . . . considering theoretical knowledge more objective than
immediate experience. A theory is something other than myself. It may be
set out on paper as a system, of rules, and it is the more truly a
theory the more completely it can be put down in such terms” (Polanyi
1974: 4).

Polanyi’s (1974: 3-9) discussion of the Copernican Revolution uses
different language to state some of the significant themes visible in
Varian (1997), Deming (1986, 1993), and McNeil (1993). These address
such concepts as descriptive richness, theory as a guide to discovery,
and modeling. As a guide to theory construction, this is also linked to
Herbert Blumer’s idea of sensitizing concepts (Blumer 1969, esp. ch. 1;
see also Baugh 1990, van den Hoonard 1997). All of these possibilities
require explicit knowledge, rendered articulate for shared communication
and reflection.

Rendering the tacit explicit is a crucial act of communication that
shapes research and the research cultures we build in any field. Only by
articulating what we know in some way do we enable others to take it in
and adapt or adopt it as their own knowledge. The complaint of novice
scholars in design research that we are “privileging the text” in a way
that somehow devalues design has it all wrong. Only through explicit
communication do we help others to access our knowledge so that they may
themselves transform what would otherwise be the raw data of artifact or
experience into information on which they may act to create knowledge.
(This involves a series of issues and distinctions I don’t propose to
elaborate here. I have discussed the nature of knowledge and the
distinctions among data, information, and knowledge elsewhere, f.ex., in
Friedman [1998] or Friedman and Olaisen [1999]).

One of the little noted points in many design research debates is the
fact that reflective practice itself rests on explicit knowledge rather
than on tacit knowledge. While Schon’s concept of reflective practice is
not a method of theorizing, (1991: 5-11), but it does raise many
questions on the kinds of thinking and reflection that contribute to
effective practice in many fields. Central to most of these is the
struggle of rendering tacit knowledge explicit in some way. While Schon
(1994: 9) suggests that there may be more possibilities for reflection
than words alone, he clearly distinguishes between the epistemology of
theoretical research and reflective inquiry.


Research Into, By, aMuch of this confusion is linked to the ambiguous definition of design
research proposed by Frayling in 1993. Frayling (1993) suggested that
there are three models of design research, research into design,
research by design, and research for design. Frayling is unclear about
what “research by design” actually means and he seems never to have
defined the term in an operational way. In a 1997 discussion (UK Council
1997: 21), he notes that it is “distantly derived from Herbert Read’s
famous teaching through art and teaching to art.” This leads to serious
conceptual problems.

Read’s (1944, 1974) distinctions deal with education and with pedagogy,
not with research. The failure to distinguish between pedagogy and
research is a significant weak area in the argument for the concept of
research by design. In addition to the difficulties this has caused in
debates on the notion of the practice-based Ph.D., it also creates
confusion for those who have come to believe that practice is research.
The confusion rests, again, on a failure to read.

Frayling’s proposal seems to be have been an effort to establish
possible new research categories. As an inquiry or probe, this is a
worthy effort. The problem arises among those who mistake an
intellectual probe with a statement of fact. To suggest that such a
category is possible does not mean that it exists in reality. Dragons
may exist, but we have no evidence that they do. Medieval mapmakers
created great confusion and limited the growth of knowledge for many
years by filling in the empty edges of their maps with such phrases as
“here there be dragons” rather than admitting, “we know nothing about
what lies beyond this point.” 

Beyond this arises the problem of what “research by design” might mean.
If such a category did exist – and it may not – the fact of an existing
category would tell us nothing of its contents. Unlike dragons, we know
that the planet Jupiter exists. Like the edges of the map, however, we
know relatively little about conditions on the surface of the planet.
Even though the laws of nature mean that some facts must be known –
gravity and pressure, for example – these facts tell us little about the
myriad realities that may play out depending on specific factors. 

As a probe, Frayling’s discussion was intended to open possibilities.
Those who mistake it for a report mistake its potential value.

In one important sense, however, Frayling seriously misunderstood Read.
He used the surface structure of Read’s terms without acknowledging a
crucial explicit distinction in Read’s approach. Read was not describing
practice-based research. He was describing practice-based education.

Education takes place through direct practice. This is true in art and
in design. This is the case in socialization and modeling, in guild
training, and it is the basis of apprenticeship (Friedman 1997: 55,
61-65; Byrne, and Sands 2002). In many situations, education and
learning proceed by practicing an art or craft. One can also learn the
art and craft of research by practicing research. Nevertheless, one does
not undertake research simply by practicing the art or craft to which
the research field is linked. 

While the phrase “research by design” has been widely used by many
people, it has not been defined. I suspect, in fact, that those who use
the phrase have not bothered to read either Frayling’s (1993) paper or
Read’s (1944, 1974) book. Instead, they adopt a misunderstood term for
its sound bite quality, linking it to an ill-defined series of notions
that equate tacit knowledge with design knowledge, proposing tacit
knowledge and design practice as a new form of theorizing. 

While these problems are relatively inconsequential outside our field,
it is important to understand them if we are to develop a foundation for
robust design research. This is why I have given them so much thought.

Again, I want to be clear on the many values of tacit knowledge. Tacit
knowledge is central to all human activity. Embodied individual and
social knowledge provides offers the existential foundation of all
activities, including intellectual inquiry. The only issue I raise here
is that tacit knowledge and reflective practice are not the basis of
research and theorizing. This is not to say, however, that there are no
relations between those different categories of construct. 


Experience and Inquiry

When ancient science was merely hypothetical and deductive, it offered
no way to select among theories. While the river civilizations of
Mesopotamia, Sumeria, Egypt, and China made great advances in practical
knowledge, administrative routine, and professional practice in many
fields, they had nothing in the way of scientific theory. Explanations
were traditional and practical or mythic (Lloyd 1970: 1-23; Cromer 1993:
throughout).

Thales proposed the first scientific theory when he suggested that the
earth was once an ocean. While he could not test his theory, what made
it scientific as contrasted with mythic was the fact that Thales
proposed a natural explanation rather than a story of divine action.

Greek mathematics offered another foundation for science, and the
Pythagoreans and Euclid built theories that are still used today. Again,
however, there were no tests. Mathematical and geometrical theories are
entirely axiomatic, and they can be tested by deduction and logic. While
empirical inquiry found a few early champions in such medieval scholars
as Robert Grosseteste and Roger Bacon, it was not until Francis Bacon
(1999, 2000) published The New Organon in 1620 that a philosophy of
science was articulated requiring a foundation in empirical observation.

At the same time, observation linked with inventive theorizing accounted
for the great advances of Copernicus, Galileo, Newtown and many more.
The tradition of empirical inquiry lies beneath two great activities in
design: design science and reflective practice. These meet in research
traditions of many kinds, including those traditions anchored in social
science and critical inquiry. 

Because I don’t propose to go on to describe a philosophy of science, I
will not explain how or why this is so, and I will not develop an
argument for any specific research tradition or the kinds of theory
construction on which a tradition might be established. I merely point
to the fact that explicit and articulate statements are the basis of all
theoretical activities, all theorizing, and all theory construction.

This true of interpretive and hermeneutical traditions, psychological,
historical, and sociological traditions, and it is as true of these as
of quantitative research in chemistry, descriptive biology or research
engineering, logistics, and axiomatic mathematics. The languages are
different. Nevertheless, in each case, only explicit articulation
permits us to contrast theories and to share them. Only explicit
articulation allows us to test, consider or reflect on the theories we
develop. For this reason, the misguided effort to link the reflective
practice of design to design knowledge, and the misguided effort to
propose tacit knowledge or direct making as a research method must
inevitably lead to dead ends.


Concluding Notes

This is a side-track to the conversation as a whole. I wanted to post it
rather than let yet another casual reference to Frayling’s proposal
drift by unnoticed.

This is not a critique of an idea that might have had promise fifteen
years ago when Prof. Frayling first suggested it. It is a critique of
those who never bothered to read Frayling, who never read the earlier
work by Sir Herbert Read on which Frayling based his proposal, and never
bothered to think these issues through in a process of critical inquiry.

It’s time to put “research into design, research by design, and research
for design” out to pasture.

Ken

Ken Friedman
Professor, Ph.D., Dr.Sci. (hc), FDRS

Dean, Swinburne Design
Swinburne University of Technology
MelbBacon, Francis. 1999. Selected Philosophical Works. Edited with an
introduction by Rose-Mary Sargent. Indianapolis, Indiana: Hackett
Publishing Company.

Bacon, Francis. 2000. The New Organon. Edited by Lisa Jardine and
Michael Silverthorne. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 

Baugh, Kenneth, Jr. 1990. The Methodology of Herbert Blumer. Critical
Interpretation and Repair. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Blumer, Herbert. 1969. Symbolic Interactionism. Perspective and Method.
Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall, Inc.

Bourdieu, Pierre. 1977. Outline of the Theory of Practice. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.

Bourdieu, Pierre. 1990. The Logic of Practice. Palo Alto, California:
Stanford University Press.

Byrne, Bryan, and Ed Sands. 2002. “Designing Collaborative Corporate
Cultures.” In Creating Breakthrough Ideas, Bryan Byrne and Susan E.
Squires, editors. Westport, Connecticut: Greenwood Publishing Group.
Chaiklin, Seth, and Jean Lave. 1993. Understanding Practice.
Perspectives on Activity and Context. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.

Cromer, Alan. 1993. Uncommon Sense. The Heretical Nature of Science.
Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Deming, W. Edwards. 1986. Out of the Crisis. Quality, Productivity and
Competitive Position. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Deming, W. Edwards. 1993. The New Economics for Industry, Government,
Education. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Massachusetts Institute of
Technology, Center for Advanced Engineering Study.

Frayling, Christopher. 1993. Research in Art and Design. RCA Research
Papers, vol. 1, no. 1. London: Royal College of Art.

Friedman, Ken. 1997. “Design Science and Design Education.” In The
Challenge of Complexity. Peter McGrory, ed. Helsinki: University of Art
and Design Helsinki, 54-72.

Friedman, Ken. 1998. “Information, Place and Policy.” Built Environment.
24: 2/3, 83-103.

Friedman, Ken. 2001. “Creating Design Knowledge: From Research into
Practice.” In Design and Technology Educational Research and
Development: The Emerging International Research Agenda. E. W. L. Norman
and P. H. Roberts, eds. Loughborough, UK: Department of Design and
Technology, Loughborough University, 31-69.

Friedman, Ken, and Johan Olaisen. 1999. “Knowledge management.” In
Underveis til fremtiden. Kunnskapsledelse i teori og praksis. Ken
Friedman and Johan Olaisen, eds. Bergen-Sandvika: Fagbokforlaget, 14-29.

Lloyd, G. E. R. 1970. Early Greek Science. Thales to Aristotle. New
York: W. W. Norton and Company.

McNeil, Donald H. 1993. “Reframing systemic paradigms for the art of
learning.” Conference of the American Society for Cybernetics.

Nonaka, Ikujiro, and Hirotaka Takeuchi. 1995. The Knowledge-Creating
Company. How Japanese Companies Create the Dynamics of Innovation. New
York: Oxford University Press.

Polanyi, Michael. 1966. The Tacit Dimension. Garden City, New York:
Doubleday and Company.

Polanyi, Michael. 1974. Personal Knowledge. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.

Read, Herbert. 1944. Education through Art. London: Faber and Faber.

Read, Herbert. 1974. Education through Art. Third revised edition. New
York: Pantheon Books.

Schon, Donald A. 1991. The Reflective Turn. Case Studies In and On
Educational Practice. New York: Teachers College Press.

UK Council for Graduate Education. 1997. Practice-Based Doctorates in
the Creative and Performing Arts and Design Workshop. Coventry: UK
Council for Graduate Education.

Van den Hoonard, Will C. 1997. Working with Sensitizing Concepts.
Analytical Field Research. Thousand Oaks: Sage Publications.

Varian, Hal R. 1997. “How to Build an Economic Model in Your Spare Time.”
Passion and Craft. Economists at Work. Michael Szenberg, editor. Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press.



-----
Swinburne University of Technology
CRICOS Provider Code: 00111D

NOTICE
This e-mail and any attachments are confidential and intended only for
the use of the addressee. They may contain information trecipient, any dissemination, distribution, printing, copying or use is
strictly prohibited. The University does not warrant that this e-mail
and any attachments are secure and there is also a risk that it may be
corrupted in transmission. It is your responsibility to check any
attachments for viruses or defects before opening them. If you have
received this transmission in error, please contact us on +61 3 9214
8000 and delete it immediately from your system. We do not accept
liability in connection with computer virus, data corruption, delay,
interruption, unauthorised access or unauthorised amendment.

Please consider the environment before printing this email.

Top of Message | Previous Page | Permalink

JiscMail Tools


RSS Feeds and Sharing


Advanced Options


Archives

April 2024
March 2024
February 2024
January 2024
December 2023
November 2023
October 2023
September 2023
August 2023
July 2023
June 2023
May 2023
April 2023
March 2023
February 2023
January 2023
December 2022
November 2022
October 2022
September 2022
August 2022
July 2022
June 2022
May 2022
April 2022
March 2022
February 2022
January 2022
December 2021
November 2021
October 2021
September 2021
August 2021
July 2021
June 2021
May 2021
April 2021
March 2021
February 2021
January 2021
December 2020
November 2020
October 2020
September 2020
August 2020
July 2020
June 2020
May 2020
April 2020
March 2020
February 2020
January 2020
December 2019
November 2019
October 2019
September 2019
August 2019
July 2019
June 2019
May 2019
April 2019
March 2019
February 2019
January 2019
December 2018
November 2018
October 2018
September 2018
August 2018
July 2018
June 2018
May 2018
April 2018
March 2018
February 2018
January 2018
December 2017
November 2017
October 2017
September 2017
August 2017
July 2017
June 2017
May 2017
April 2017
March 2017
February 2017
January 2017
December 2016
November 2016
October 2016
September 2016
August 2016
July 2016
June 2016
May 2016
April 2016
March 2016
February 2016
January 2016
December 2015
November 2015
October 2015
September 2015
August 2015
July 2015
June 2015
May 2015
April 2015
March 2015
February 2015
January 2015
December 2014
November 2014
October 2014
September 2014
August 2014
July 2014
June 2014
May 2014
April 2014
March 2014
February 2014
January 2014
December 2013
November 2013
October 2013
September 2013
August 2013
July 2013
June 2013
May 2013
April 2013
March 2013
February 2013
January 2013
December 2012
November 2012
October 2012
September 2012
August 2012
July 2012
June 2012
May 2012
April 2012
March 2012
February 2012
January 2012
December 2011
November 2011
October 2011
September 2011
August 2011
July 2011
June 2011
May 2011
April 2011
March 2011
February 2011
January 2011
December 2010
November 2010
October 2010
September 2010
August 2010
July 2010
June 2010
May 2010
April 2010
March 2010
February 2010
January 2010
December 2009
November 2009
October 2009
September 2009
August 2009
July 2009
June 2009
May 2009
April 2009
March 2009
February 2009
January 2009
December 2008
November 2008
October 2008
September 2008
August 2008
July 2008
June 2008
May 2008
April 2008
March 2008
February 2008
January 2008
December 2007
November 2007
October 2007
September 2007
August 2007
July 2007
June 2007
May 2007
April 2007
March 2007
February 2007
January 2007
2006
2005
2004
2003
2002
2001
2000
1999
1998


JiscMail is a Jisc service.

View our service policies at https://www.jiscmail.ac.uk/policyandsecurity/ and Jisc's privacy policy at https://www.jisc.ac.uk/website/privacy-notice

For help and support help@jisc.ac.uk

Secured by F-Secure Anti-Virus CataList Email List Search Powered by the LISTSERV Email List Manager