JiscMail Logo
Email discussion lists for the UK Education and Research communities

Help for FILM-PHILOSOPHY Archives


FILM-PHILOSOPHY Archives

FILM-PHILOSOPHY Archives


FILM-PHILOSOPHY@JISCMAIL.AC.UK


View:

Message:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Topic:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Author:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

Font:

Proportional Font

LISTSERV Archives

LISTSERV Archives

FILM-PHILOSOPHY Home

FILM-PHILOSOPHY Home

FILM-PHILOSOPHY  2002

FILM-PHILOSOPHY 2002

Options

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Log In

Log In

Get Password

Get Password

Subject:

6.20 Smith on McGinn

From:

[log in to unmask]

Reply-To:

Film-Philosophy Salon <[log in to unmask]>

Date:

Fri, 16 Aug 2002 17:43:53 +0100

Content-Type:

text/plain

Parts/Attachments:

Parts/Attachments

text/plain (69 lines)

_______ F i l m - P h i l o s o p h y

_______ ISSN 1466-4615
_______ Journal | Salon | Portal
_______ PO Box 26161, London SW8 4WD
_______ http://www.film-philosophy.com

_______ vol. 6 no. 20, August 2002




Murray Smith

The Bad and the Beautiful


Colin McGinn
_Ethics, Evil, and Fiction_
Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1997
ISBN 0198237162 (hb) 0198238770 (pb)
x + 186 pp.

McGinn's book is a book of two halves. While the first part constitutes an essay on the nature of morality in general, and evil in particular, the second part dwells on the relationship between morality and aesthetics, especially as these phenomena are explored and revealed through works of fiction. These two halves are framed by considerations of 'method' in moral philosophy: what, McGinn asks, is the appropriate form of discourse for the investigation of moral life? McGinn argues that the significance of fictional discourse for moral thinking has never been properly taken on board by moral philosophy; his aim in this book is to suggest how moral philosophy might properly accommodate fiction's moral dimension.

Over the first two major chapters ('Goodness' and 'Knowledge of Goodness'), McGinn mounts a defence of moral realism along with a critique of dispositional theories of morality which reduce moral concepts and values to psychological ones. This is then bolstered by a comparison between moral and scientific knowledge, through which McGinn aims to demonstrate that moral knowledge is at least as robust as scientific knowledge; moral knowledge may be different in nature from scientific knowledge, but it is not 'epistemologically queer'. The basic strategy here is to show that the supposedly unique fragility, or fallibility, of moral knowledge only arises in the context of a highly-dubious empiricist metaphysics, which measures all types of knowledge by the single, arbitrarily privileged yardstick of knowledge-through-sense-experience. Moving closer to the target of the second part of the book, 'The Evil Character' sets forth an investigation and analysis of the moral psychology of evil. McGinn begins with an abstract formula for a type of being for whom the pain of others is pleasurable ('the evil who are happy', as Nietzsche described such persons), and the pleasure of others is painful. He then goes on to survey a range of actual and imagined types of immoral behaviour, including sadism (analysed in terms of the power and pleasure derived from destroying the most basic values of the victim -- above all, her attachment to life itself), cruelty motivated by envy, revenge, rivalry, as well as 'primitive evil' -- a brute pleasure in the pain of others for its own sake.

From the point of view of aesthetics, the next chapter, 'Beauty of Soul', is the pivotal chapter in the study. Drawing on Thomas Reid, McGinn argues that the mind (or 'soul', in the language he inherits from Reid) and moral character of an individual possess aesthetic qualities (and thus, by extension, that aesthetic qualities are not restricted to objects of perception). This claim is buttressed by the pervasiveness, in ordinary language, of 'aesthetic-moral' terms -- words which deliver moral judgements by attributing aesthetic qualities to the object of judgement: you might say that someone's behaviour 'stinks', or that someone has a 'sweet' personality, for example. (I cannot resist citing another piece of evidence in support of this thesis, from Hanif Kureishi's _The Buddha of Suburbia_: 'But you're not ugly inside', says Jamila to the unprepossessing Changez. 'Yes, inside I look like Shashi Kapoor, I know that for sure', he replies.) The final two major chapters then pursue the implications of this thesis, which McGinn dubs the *aesthetic theory of virtue* (ATV), through two complementary literary case studies (thus making good on his ambition to bring together two modes of moral investigation -- metaethical analysis and the moral exegesis of fiction). 'The Picture: Dorian Gray' examines Wilde's novel in which outward beauty co-exists with ugliness of soul, in part as a means of testing the *amoral aestheticism* for which Wilde is (somewhat misleadingly) famed. Noting that all human lives run 'on separate aesthetic rails' (145) -- beauty of body and of soul -- McGinn turns his attention to another case of radical 'aesthetic bifurcation' (117), though one which inverts the polarities of _Dorian Gray_: the conjunction of a monstrous body with inner beauty in the monster of Mary Shelley's _Frankenstein_. If in the first case we see the corruption of soul by the overvaluing of outer beauty, in the second we witness the destruction of soul by outward ugliness -- insofar as the initially gentle and generous monster is driven to revenge (an evil state of mind on McGinn's analysis, if not the most nefarious) by the hostile reactions of others to his appearance. (Changez continues in _The Buddha of Suburbia_: 'But some people are really ugly pig-faces, and they have a terrible time and all. I'm beginning a national campaign to stop this prejudice.') The existential difficulties and moral dangers of our aesthetically-riven existence lie at the heart of both cases.

McGinn pairs the ATV with a complementary thesis (developed on the basis of Nabokov's remarks on 'aesthetic bliss' in the Afterword to _Lolita_). Call this the *moral theory of beauty*, or MTB: 'an object is beautiful if and only if it affords aesthetic bliss, and aesthetic bliss is a state of mind in which one is connected to other states of being in which art is the norm -- where art involves curiosity, tenderness, kindness, and ecstasy' (110), these qualities all being construed as moral ones. McGinn is clear that the ATV and MTB taken together are not intended to reduce morality to aesthetics or vice versa, but rather to show how intimately and systematically the two are interrelated: 'The ATV takes us from morality to aesthetics, while Nabokov's formula takes us from aesthetics to morality: the upshot is that morality leads back to itself, after taking a detour through aesthetics' (111-2). This culminates in the case for *moral aestheticism*, as a superior alternative to the amoral aestheticism examined in _Dorian Gray_: 'The true aesthete must be a moralist, since he cares about the beauty of his soul' (139), as well as the beauty of appearance.

Where does this leave aesthetics ? The MTB is introduced as a subordinate thesis, designed to show us how the 'beauty' of a virtuous person takes us through aesthetics and back to morality. But it is also a thesis about the nature of aesthetic experience, and since McGinn adheres here to what he calls 'panaestheticism' ('We are aesthetic beings through and through; we apprehend the world through aesthetic eyes' (121)), one must ask: just how tight is the fit between morality and aesthetics? Compared with the precision with which McGinn discusses the relationship between psychological and moral concepts earlier in the book, the discussion here, though never less than stimulating, is relatively loose. There are hints that McGinn doesn't regard the MTB as an exhaustive theory of beauty, that aesthetics can't be equated with or reduced to questions of beauty, and that morality and aesthetics 'do not exist in perfect harmony' (141). But the formal statement of the MTB as it stands allows precious little space for any aesthetic quality or experience which does not lead us to a moral quality, or have a moral dimension. We are warned, for example, that architectural forms, or the patterns and rhythms of modern city life, might not just be exhilarating or unpleasant, but morally edifying or corrupting. By the time that we reach the statement that 'the better a society's taste in outer things, the better placed it will be to promote virtue' (120), one feels an urgent need to know just what the moral status of (say) platform shoes and long hair is, and how one would decide this matter.

McGinn's own examples, and indeed his own notion of aesthetic bifurcation, suggest how much of aesthetic experience escapes the zone of overlap between the moral and the aesthetic. One of the lessons of both _Dorian Gray_ and _Lolita_ is that there are types of beauty -- physical, perceivable beauty -- that don't reliably tell us anything about the moral character of the person or thing exhibiting them. It is precisely because physical beauty may tell us nothing about a person's moral character that we can be betrayed by it. If a harmonious appearance necessarily carried some sort of moral implication, then in being swayed by the handsome charmer we would not really be deceived, or at least not so devastatingly, for we would be responding to something morally good (and not merely aesthetically pleasing) in that person. These aesthetic-moral virtues might co-exist in that person with other moral defects of character, but they would themselves be moral virtues. The challenge, then, is to the comprehensiveness of the MTB, and to the exclusivity of the circuit which McGinn argues runs between morality and aesthetics. No doubt there is significant interconnection; but surely the aesthetic network runs off in other, non-moral directions as well.

A recurring worry for McGinn, which arises out of his analysis of the evil moral psychology (one for whom the pain of others causes pleasure, and the pleasure of others causes pain), is 'entertainment'. Usually McGinn's chosen examples are modern media (movies and TV), where we find pleasure in depictions of violence, disaster, and suffering. But the problem never comes properly into focus. The vast majority of mass media representations are, in one way, very conservative: where spectacular, graphic violence is represented as something to take pleasure in, it is the violence of revenge against figures of evil. True, revenge is one of McGinn's evils; but in that case the problem extends back through history to vast swathes of representation in all media. McGinn's chief examples, _Dorian Gray_ and _Frankenstein_, are full of appalling moral acts, but both works afford considerable pleasure. Taking some form of pleasure in representations of suffering or evil -- as we do from forms like tragedy, the sublime, and horror, which depend on negative emotions, or dystopian fictions which depict wholly undesirable states of affairs -- is a long-standing problem in aesthetic debate. But the problem surely isn't that these forms might promulgate sadism or detached aestheticism -- McGinn's worries -- but that we (non-sadists) can find some sort of satisfaction and pleasure in such depressing things. McGinn's use of the word 'entertainment' seems to play the purely rhetorical role of separating worthy, legitimate depictions of evil and illegitimate ones, as if 'art' and 'entertainment' were mutually exclusive terms, when they clearly are not. Most of the difficult questions, concerning how we evaluate a depiction of evil which gives us pleasure, are left unaddressed. The simple conjunction of depictions of evil with pleasure in those depictions tells us very little; responding with pleasure to a work can't be assumed to equate with responding with pleasure to an evil act or character within the work.

McGinn's book is a bracing read, raising challenging questions and proposing provocative, intriguing, and often compelling solutions in equal measure. Written with considerable verve, the tone of the book is nevertheless uneven. While there are many passages of meticulous argumentation, at times McGinn comes across as a querulous moralist. The book is also compact, more like a sustained essay than a comprehensive statement, and some disappointments arise from its impatient momentum. McGinn shares with Martha Nussbaum an emphasis on the value of fictional explorations of moral life in stressing specificity over abstract prescription. While acknowledging an overlap in interest, however, McGinn hurries us by the likeness, devoting no space whatsoever to a comparison. Similarly, Hegelian objections to the 'beautiful soul' are swept aside as 'obscure' -- a little odd, since Hegel characterizes this state of being as a sort of moral narcissism, a problem that McGinn does address. It is testimony to the interest and originality of McGinn's book, though, that one is left wanting more of it, so that the gaps and difficulties touched on here might be more fully addressed.

University of Kent at Canterbury, England


Copyright © _Film-Philosophy_ 2002

Murray Smith, 'The Bad and the Beautiful', _Film-Philosophy_, vol. 6 no. 20, August 2002 <http://www.film-philosophy.com/vol6-2002/n20smith>.

_______ _______


_Film-Philosophy_ ejournal texts are published through the email salon so that they can be discussed and contested and continued by you members, so please send your thoughts to:

    [log in to unmask]

_______ _______ _______


To change to digest, send the message: set film-philosophy digest
to: [log in to unmask]

To leave, send the message: leave film-philosophy
to: [log in to unmask]

If you have problems unsubscribing, or sending messages generally, then do not ask for help via the salon, but simply email the owner at:
[log in to unmask]
or
[log in to unmask]

_______ _______ _______ _______

Top of Message | Previous Page | Permalink

JiscMail Tools


RSS Feeds and Sharing


Advanced Options


Archives

April 2024
March 2024
February 2024
January 2024
December 2023
November 2023
October 2023
September 2023
August 2023
July 2023
June 2023
May 2023
April 2023
March 2023
February 2023
January 2023
December 2022
November 2022
October 2022
September 2022
August 2022
July 2022
June 2022
May 2022
April 2022
March 2022
February 2022
January 2022
December 2021
November 2021
October 2021
September 2021
August 2021
July 2021
June 2021
May 2021
April 2021
March 2021
February 2021
January 2021
December 2020
November 2020
October 2020
September 2020
August 2020
July 2020
June 2020
May 2020
April 2020
March 2020
February 2020
January 2020
December 2019
November 2019
October 2019
September 2019
August 2019
July 2019
June 2019
May 2019
April 2019
March 2019
February 2019
January 2019
December 2018
November 2018
October 2018
September 2018
August 2018
July 2018
June 2018
May 2018
April 2018
March 2018
February 2018
January 2018
December 2017
November 2017
October 2017
September 2017
August 2017
July 2017
June 2017
May 2017
April 2017
March 2017
February 2017
January 2017
December 2016
November 2016
October 2016
September 2016
August 2016
July 2016
June 2016
May 2016
April 2016
March 2016
February 2016
January 2016
December 2015
November 2015
October 2015
September 2015
August 2015
July 2015
June 2015
May 2015
April 2015
March 2015
February 2015
January 2015
December 2014
November 2014
October 2014
September 2014
August 2014
July 2014
June 2014
May 2014
April 2014
March 2014
February 2014
January 2014
December 2013
November 2013
October 2013
September 2013
August 2013
July 2013
June 2013
May 2013
April 2013
March 2013
February 2013
January 2013
December 2012
November 2012
October 2012
September 2012
August 2012
July 2012
June 2012
May 2012
April 2012
March 2012
February 2012
January 2012
December 2011
November 2011
October 2011
September 2011
August 2011
July 2011
June 2011
May 2011
April 2011
March 2011
February 2011
January 2011
December 2010
November 2010
October 2010
September 2010
August 2010
July 2010
June 2010
May 2010
April 2010
March 2010
February 2010
January 2010
December 2009
November 2009
October 2009
September 2009
August 2009
July 2009
June 2009
May 2009
April 2009
March 2009
February 2009
January 2009
December 2008
November 2008
October 2008
September 2008
August 2008
July 2008
June 2008
May 2008
April 2008
March 2008
February 2008
January 2008
December 2007
November 2007
October 2007
September 2007
August 2007
July 2007
June 2007
May 2007
April 2007
March 2007
February 2007
January 2007
2006
2005
2004
2003
2002
2001
2000
1999
1998


JiscMail is a Jisc service.

View our service policies at https://www.jiscmail.ac.uk/policyandsecurity/ and Jisc's privacy policy at https://www.jisc.ac.uk/website/privacy-notice

For help and support help@jisc.ac.uk

Secured by F-Secure Anti-Virus CataList Email List Search Powered by the LISTSERV Email List Manager