JiscMail Logo
Email discussion lists for the UK Education and Research communities

Help for PHD-DESIGN Archives


PHD-DESIGN Archives

PHD-DESIGN Archives


PHD-DESIGN@JISCMAIL.AC.UK


View:

Message:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Topic:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Author:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

Font:

Proportional Font

LISTSERV Archives

LISTSERV Archives

PHD-DESIGN Home

PHD-DESIGN Home

PHD-DESIGN  February 2016

PHD-DESIGN February 2016

Options

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Log In

Log In

Get Password

Get Password

Subject:

Re: Assume fixed number of colours in design?

From:

Ken Friedman <[log in to unmask]>

Reply-To:

PhD-Design - This list is for discussion of PhD studies and related research in Design <[log in to unmask]>

Date:

Fri, 19 Feb 2016 22:44:51 +0100

Content-Type:

text/plain

Parts/Attachments:

Parts/Attachments

text/plain (100 lines)

Friends,

Terry Love’s question does not make sense to me. Martins reasonable response asks Terry the right question: “Could you elaborate on what those 'strong reasons' are? … I am wondering whether you mean that, even if we can't know something, we should pretend that we do in order to facilitate theory?”

What do we mean when we speaks of a theory? In my view, a theory is a model of the world. Useful theories tell us something about the things we look at. They offer information on things we try to understand. Depending on the nature and level of the theories that we use, theories always involve a choice of position and views, and all theories entail theoretical presuppositions and methodological presuppositions. Since this is so, it is useful for a theory to capture the properties of the world. I’ve discussed my view of these issues in an article on theory construction (Friedman 2003). The article provides information on what a theory is and how a theory ought to work. You will find a copy in the papers section of my Academia page at URL:

https://swinburne.academia.edu/KenFriedman

The problem of any kind of theory is that no theory can map the full world without being as large as the world it maps. To create reasonably parsimonious theory, therefore, we must abstract features of the world — choosing what to leave in our maps and models while deciding what to leave out. Hal Varian (1997), professor emeritus of economics at Berkeley and chief economist at Google, discusses some of these issue in a useful article on how to build economic models.

Two very useful articles on these issues are Herbert Blumer’s (1969) discussion of the methodological perspective of symbolic interactionism, and an article by Robert Sutton and Barry Staw (1995) on what theory is not. (The real Don Norman sent me the Sutton & Staw article.)

You will find copies of these in the teaching papers section of my Academia page at URL:

https://swinburne.academia.edu/KenFriedman

They will be accesible until March 1.

Anyone interested in developing theory will find these useful. To generate theory, it is vital to state our explicit assumptions and make available the information on which we shape our models. The problem with Terry’s post is that he claims strong reasons without stating them. I’m not going to addressing the specific problem Terry brings forward because the question is not framed in a way precise enough to be useful in theory construction. 

Why, precisely, “Is it better to assume as an axiom in making design theory that colour always comprises a set of fixed colours rather than assuming colour as being a continuous spectrum?"

If we were to adopt this assumption, how, precisely would we determine what colours belong in this set?

What strong reasons make these claims reasonable? 

The shape of this argument is extremely weak. It starts as a question, but it’s not really a question. It’s actually a thesis. Terry opens with a question in an effort to back us into a debate. Nevertheless, Terry does not state his thesis. Neither does he offer an account of the strong reasons he claims. Terry’s post opens with a statement masquerading as a question. It neglects to account for the premises and assumptions, and then asks for thoughts and comments.

My thoughts resemble Martin’s, and my comment is that an effort to develop serious theory requires a better way of asking questions.   

Martin caught the unreal aspect of this when he asked, “I am wondering whether you mean that, even if we can't know something, we should pretend that we do in order to facilitate theory?”

There are two reasonable answers to this question, and an unreasonable answer. One reasonable answer is that we can pretend to know something to facilitate theories that may be useful in a thought experiment. That’s not the case here. In this case, Terry is making the claim to strong reasons, that is, he is claiming that this proposal will help us better to understand the real world of design choices.  

Another reasonable answer is that we can pretend to know something we cannot know to facilitate theories that have no meaning. Everyone knows the urban legend of the physics student (or engineering student) who gets the only A in his section by answering the question “Is hell exothermic or endothermic.” (If you don’t know it, Google it. There are many versions from gently amusing to utterly bawdy.) But the real question has no meaning. This also occurs in an intriguing and theoretically profound answer to the Scholastic question about how many angels can dance on the point of a pin. Anders Sandberg’s (2001) treatment of “Quantum Gravity Treatment of the Angel Density Problem” is, indeed, a thought experiment. It is neither meaningless nor real — what makes this imaginary paper meaningful is that Sandberg defines his assumptions explicitly. Terry doesn’t do this either.

There is a third answer to Martin’s question. It is the one answer we generally do not accept as a basis for research. That answer is, “Because I say so.” It’s not clear that Terry is simply saying we are supposed to believe in his strong reasons because he says so, but so far, that’s all the evidence we see.

If we are to take seriously a claim to theory, it is vital to state out assumptions and evidence. Any post that claims strong reasons for theory should provide the evidence on which those claims rest and state the assumptions that lead to valid theory.     
 
Yours,

Ken

Ken Friedman, PhD, DSc (hc), FDRS | Editor-in-Chief | 设计 She Ji. The Journal of Design, Economics, and Innovation | Published by Tongji University in Cooperation with Elsevier | URL: http://www.journals.elsevier.com/she-ji-the-journal-of-design-economics-and-innovation/

Chair Professor of Design Innovation Studies | College of Design and Innovation | Tongji University | Shanghai, China ||| University Distinguished Professor | Centre for Design Innovation | Swinburne University of Technology | Melbourne, Australia ||| 

—

References

Blumer, Herbert. 1969. Symbolic Interactionism. Perspective and Method. Englewood Cliffs, New Jersey: Prentice-Hall Inc., pp. 1-60.

Friedman, Ken. 2003. “Theory construction in design research: criteria, approaches, and methods.” Design Studies, 24 (2003), 507–522. DOI:
http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/S0142-694X(03)00039-5

Sandberg, Anders. 2001. “Quantum Gravity Treatment of the Angel Density Problem.” Annals of Improbable Research. URL:
http://www.improbable.com/airchives/paperair/volume7/v7i3/angels-7-3.htm
Accessed 2016 February 19.

Sutton, Robert I., and Barry M. Staw. 1995. "What Theory is Not." Administrative Science Quarterly, Vol. 40, No. 3 (Sep.), pp. 371-384

Varian, Hal R. 1997. “How to Build and Economic Model in Your Spare Time.” The American Economist, Vol. 41, No. 2 (Fall), pp. 3-10.

--

Martin Salisbury wrote:

—snip—

Could you elaborate on what those 'strong reasons' are?

When trying to get to the bottom of how many colours are distinguishable by the human eye, we tend to encounter those dreaded words, ‘experts estimate ...' followed by any anything from 100,000 to 10 million. And of course perception of colour varies from individual to individual. I am wondering whether you mean that, even if we can't know something, we should pretend that we do in order to facilitate theory?

—snip—

—

Terry Love wrote:

—snip—

Is it better to assume as an axiom in making design theory that colour always comprises a set of fixed colours rather than assuming colour as being a continuous spectrum?

There seem to be strong reasons in theory and practice to make this assumption, and that it is possible calculate exactly how big the set is (i.e exactly how many different colours) for each design scenario.

The advantage in design theory and research is between fixed and known variety and 'infinite' variety.

—snip—

--


-----------------------------------------------------------------
PhD-Design mailing list  <[log in to unmask]>
Discussion of PhD studies and related research in Design
Subscribe or Unsubscribe at https://www.jiscmail.ac.uk/phd-design
-----------------------------------------------------------------

Top of Message | Previous Page | Permalink

JiscMail Tools


RSS Feeds and Sharing


Advanced Options


Archives

May 2024
April 2024
March 2024
February 2024
January 2024
December 2023
November 2023
October 2023
September 2023
August 2023
July 2023
June 2023
May 2023
April 2023
March 2023
February 2023
January 2023
December 2022
November 2022
October 2022
September 2022
August 2022
July 2022
June 2022
May 2022
April 2022
March 2022
February 2022
January 2022
December 2021
November 2021
October 2021
September 2021
August 2021
July 2021
June 2021
May 2021
April 2021
March 2021
February 2021
January 2021
December 2020
November 2020
October 2020
September 2020
August 2020
July 2020
June 2020
May 2020
April 2020
March 2020
February 2020
January 2020
December 2019
November 2019
October 2019
September 2019
August 2019
July 2019
June 2019
May 2019
April 2019
March 2019
February 2019
January 2019
December 2018
November 2018
October 2018
September 2018
August 2018
July 2018
June 2018
May 2018
April 2018
March 2018
February 2018
January 2018
December 2017
November 2017
October 2017
September 2017
August 2017
July 2017
June 2017
May 2017
April 2017
March 2017
February 2017
January 2017
December 2016
November 2016
October 2016
September 2016
August 2016
July 2016
June 2016
May 2016
April 2016
March 2016
February 2016
January 2016
December 2015
November 2015
October 2015
September 2015
August 2015
July 2015
June 2015
May 2015
April 2015
March 2015
February 2015
January 2015
December 2014
November 2014
October 2014
September 2014
August 2014
July 2014
June 2014
May 2014
April 2014
March 2014
February 2014
January 2014
December 2013
November 2013
October 2013
September 2013
August 2013
July 2013
June 2013
May 2013
April 2013
March 2013
February 2013
January 2013
December 2012
November 2012
October 2012
September 2012
August 2012
July 2012
June 2012
May 2012
April 2012
March 2012
February 2012
January 2012
December 2011
November 2011
October 2011
September 2011
August 2011
July 2011
June 2011
May 2011
April 2011
March 2011
February 2011
January 2011
December 2010
November 2010
October 2010
September 2010
August 2010
July 2010
June 2010
May 2010
April 2010
March 2010
February 2010
January 2010
December 2009
November 2009
October 2009
September 2009
August 2009
July 2009
June 2009
May 2009
April 2009
March 2009
February 2009
January 2009
December 2008
November 2008
October 2008
September 2008
August 2008
July 2008
June 2008
May 2008
April 2008
March 2008
February 2008
January 2008
December 2007
November 2007
October 2007
September 2007
August 2007
July 2007
June 2007
May 2007
April 2007
March 2007
February 2007
January 2007
2006
2005
2004
2003
2002
2001
2000
1999
1998


JiscMail is a Jisc service.

View our service policies at https://www.jiscmail.ac.uk/policyandsecurity/ and Jisc's privacy policy at https://www.jisc.ac.uk/website/privacy-notice

For help and support help@jisc.ac.uk

Secured by F-Secure Anti-Virus CataList Email List Search Powered by the LISTSERV Email List Manager