JiscMail Logo
Email discussion lists for the UK Education and Research communities

Help for FILM-PHILOSOPHY Archives


FILM-PHILOSOPHY Archives

FILM-PHILOSOPHY Archives


FILM-PHILOSOPHY@JISCMAIL.AC.UK


View:

Message:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Topic:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Author:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

Font:

Proportional Font

LISTSERV Archives

LISTSERV Archives

FILM-PHILOSOPHY Home

FILM-PHILOSOPHY Home

FILM-PHILOSOPHY  2004

FILM-PHILOSOPHY 2004

Options

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Log In

Log In

Get Password

Get Password

Subject:

Readable signs - the principle of relevance

From:

"Buckland, Warren" <[log in to unmask]>

Reply-To:

Film-Philosophy Salon <[log in to unmask]>

Date:

Mon, 2 Feb 2004 11:53:33 -0800

Content-Type:

text/plain

Parts/Attachments:

Parts/Attachments

text/plain (91 lines)

The road sign examples (reading small details in a film) do not follow
Sperber and Wilson's principle of relevance (outlined below), because
they are not the most relevant information in the image to process. When
academics read these small details, they are (deliberately?) working
against the principle of relevance.

The problem being discussed in this debate concerns WHERE to locate
meaning ? in the film itself, or in the reading strategies of
spectators. If we locate meaning in the film, we adhere to a semantic
theory of meaning. If we locate it in spectators (in their shared
schemata, as cognitivists argue), we adhere to a pragmatic theory of
meaning.

The pragmatic theory of meaning is based on the premise of
non-communication, on the premise that failure in communication is the
norm, and what needs to be explained is how successful communication
takes place. By contrast, semantics describes successful communication
as an automatic process regulated by a system of codes.

Sperber and Wilson's theory of relevance is a pragmatic theory of
meaning. The basis of Sperber and Wilson's principle of relevance lies
in the relation between what they term 'contextual effect' and
'processing effort'. The addressee will process information only if it
creates contextual effects - i.e. if it is new and relates to
information already acquired by the addressee. But the new information
will not be processed at all unless the processing effort is small.

If the new information has a large contextual effect and if, at the same
time, its processing effort is small, then it is what Sperber and Wilson
call 'relevant'. More specifically, they define relevance in terms of
two extent conditions:

Extent condition 1: an assumption is relevant in a context to the extent
that its contextual effects in this context are large.
Extent condition 2: an assumption is relevant in a context to the extent
that the effort required to process it in this context is small. (Dan
Sperber and Deirdre Wilson, Relevance: Communication and Cognition, p.
125)

Relevance is therefore a comparative concept, involving a balancing of
input (processing effort) against output (contextual effects).
Furthermore, Sperber and Wilson argue that their principle of relevance
is a universal cognitive-psychological principle of information
processing, rather than a principle that originates in socio-cultural
norms.

Only if the addressee generates the relevant inference will
communication take place. But because the principle of relevance is a
universal cognitive-psychological principle of information processing
(or 'naturalistic'), then we are hard-wired to generate the most
relevant inference. That is, for Sperber and Wilson, then, the principle
of relevance can be assumed to be mutually manifest to both sender and
addressee. This is because it is in the interest of the sender to
communicate her message by producing an utterance that will yield in the
addressee the optimal contextual effect with only a small amount of
processing effort. This, of course, is also in the interest of the
addressee, who will thus automatically generate the inference in which
such a result can be achieved, which is precisely the inference
corresponding to the sender's message.

This, then is how Sperber and Wilson define how communication takes
place. As I said above, the 'road sign' examples are working against the
principle of relevance, because they do not create the optimal
contextual effect with only a small amount of processing effort. In
fact, they seem to do the opposite - we are using a large amount of
processing effort to create a small contextual effect.


Warren Buckland
Associate Professor, Film Studies
Chapman University
School of Film and Television
One University Drive
Orange
CA 92866
USA.
phone: (714) 744 7018
fax: (714)  997 6700
Editor, "New Review of Film and Television Studies":
http://www.tandf.co.uk/journals/titles/17400309.asp
 
 

*
*
Film-Philosophy Email Discussion Salon.
After hitting 'reply' please always delete the text of the message you are replying to.
To leave, send the message: leave film-philosophy to: [log in to unmask]
For help email: [log in to unmask], not the salon.
**

Top of Message | Previous Page | Permalink

JiscMail Tools


RSS Feeds and Sharing


Advanced Options


Archives

May 2024
April 2024
March 2024
February 2024
January 2024
December 2023
November 2023
October 2023
September 2023
August 2023
July 2023
June 2023
May 2023
April 2023
March 2023
February 2023
January 2023
December 2022
November 2022
October 2022
September 2022
August 2022
July 2022
June 2022
May 2022
April 2022
March 2022
February 2022
January 2022
December 2021
November 2021
October 2021
September 2021
August 2021
July 2021
June 2021
May 2021
April 2021
March 2021
February 2021
January 2021
December 2020
November 2020
October 2020
September 2020
August 2020
July 2020
June 2020
May 2020
April 2020
March 2020
February 2020
January 2020
December 2019
November 2019
October 2019
September 2019
August 2019
July 2019
June 2019
May 2019
April 2019
March 2019
February 2019
January 2019
December 2018
November 2018
October 2018
September 2018
August 2018
July 2018
June 2018
May 2018
April 2018
March 2018
February 2018
January 2018
December 2017
November 2017
October 2017
September 2017
August 2017
July 2017
June 2017
May 2017
April 2017
March 2017
February 2017
January 2017
December 2016
November 2016
October 2016
September 2016
August 2016
July 2016
June 2016
May 2016
April 2016
March 2016
February 2016
January 2016
December 2015
November 2015
October 2015
September 2015
August 2015
July 2015
June 2015
May 2015
April 2015
March 2015
February 2015
January 2015
December 2014
November 2014
October 2014
September 2014
August 2014
July 2014
June 2014
May 2014
April 2014
March 2014
February 2014
January 2014
December 2013
November 2013
October 2013
September 2013
August 2013
July 2013
June 2013
May 2013
April 2013
March 2013
February 2013
January 2013
December 2012
November 2012
October 2012
September 2012
August 2012
July 2012
June 2012
May 2012
April 2012
March 2012
February 2012
January 2012
December 2011
November 2011
October 2011
September 2011
August 2011
July 2011
June 2011
May 2011
April 2011
March 2011
February 2011
January 2011
December 2010
November 2010
October 2010
September 2010
August 2010
July 2010
June 2010
May 2010
April 2010
March 2010
February 2010
January 2010
December 2009
November 2009
October 2009
September 2009
August 2009
July 2009
June 2009
May 2009
April 2009
March 2009
February 2009
January 2009
December 2008
November 2008
October 2008
September 2008
August 2008
July 2008
June 2008
May 2008
April 2008
March 2008
February 2008
January 2008
December 2007
November 2007
October 2007
September 2007
August 2007
July 2007
June 2007
May 2007
April 2007
March 2007
February 2007
January 2007
2006
2005
2004
2003
2002
2001
2000
1999
1998


JiscMail is a Jisc service.

View our service policies at https://www.jiscmail.ac.uk/policyandsecurity/ and Jisc's privacy policy at https://www.jisc.ac.uk/website/privacy-notice

For help and support help@jisc.ac.uk

Secured by F-Secure Anti-Virus CataList Email List Search Powered by the LISTSERV Email List Manager