JiscMail Logo
Email discussion lists for the UK Education and Research communities

Help for PHD-DESIGN Archives


PHD-DESIGN Archives

PHD-DESIGN Archives


PHD-DESIGN@JISCMAIL.AC.UK


View:

Message:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Topic:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Author:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

Font:

Proportional Font

LISTSERV Archives

LISTSERV Archives

PHD-DESIGN Home

PHD-DESIGN Home

PHD-DESIGN  2003

PHD-DESIGN 2003

Options

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Post New Message

Post New Message

Newsletter Templates

Newsletter Templates

Log Out

Log Out

Change Password

Change Password

Subject:

questions for Terry about theory

From:

Ben Matthews <[log in to unmask]>

Reply-To:

Ben Matthews <[log in to unmask]>

Date:

Wed, 19 Mar 2003 08:01:03 +1000

Content-Type:

text/plain

Parts/Attachments:

Parts/Attachments

text/plain (176 lines)

Reply

Reply

Dear Terry,

Thanks for your contributions to the theory thread on PhD-Design. I feel
that my understanding of the subtleties of the discussion is not what it
should be, and so I have a number of questions for you from your first
post that I still haven't been able to get my head around. I hope you
don't mind me chasing you up. If you have the time to respond, I'd be
grateful.

When you say that the causal explanation "of agency and behaviour lie in
understanding the physicality of how people function", I'm not sure I
understand you. It appears to me that you are advocating a (purely)
materialist explanation of human behaviour. Do I understand you
correctly?

In that case, any appeal to phenomenological categories (such as
thoughts, intentions, motivations, feelings etc.) cannot lead to any
causal explanation (as you then say); but (I think) what you imply is
that human agency can ultimately be explained (only) through physics
(which would make agency an illusion, since physical explanations are
deterministic). If that's the case, I don't then understand the role of
the phenomenological categories. While you acknowledge phenomenological
categories, you say they don't have the same ontological or
epistemological status, and cannot feature in causal explanations. Is
this a type of epiphenomenalism? Or would you say that these categories
more like obsolete linguistic conventions that we have inherited and
would be better off discarding (at least for epistemological reasons)?

Something else I don't understand: while it is surely true that
"literatures on phenomenology, critical theory, hermeneutics, grounded
theory, alternative paradigms, post-positivism, symbolic interactionism
etc can be seen as different ways of minimising ambiguity in theory", I
thought that underlying most of these was some fundamental disagreement
(among others) about the nature and role of theory in representing and
understanding (social) reality. Certainly this is the case with
phenomenology and (philosophical) hermeneutics, at least. Does this
square with your understanding? Aren't there deeper-level philosophical
disagreements as a matter of course with some of these other
perspectives that preclude them from being considered just one more
strut in some epistemological, superstructural ideal? I realise here
that I may be reading too much into your comment that these perspectives
are different ways of minimising ambiguity in theory, but this is where
Klaus' post(s) appear to have the same concern. Certain strands of
phenomenology and hermeneutics explicitly deal with some of Klaus'
points, such as creating/maintaining a role for human agency, and
dissolving the Cartesian, dispassionate-subject view of knowledge of the
external world.

I'd also like to query your usage of the term "theory". Again, depending
on how well (or not) I understand you, I think you use "theory" to be
equivalent to "causal explanation". I get this impression from your
comments concerning correlatory representations (you don't say
"correlatory theories"). In referring, for instance, to Schon's work as
constructing correlatory representation (rather than constructing
theory), perhaps I am gaining a glimpse of the radically different usage
of "theory" that you envision to be epistemologically useful. If Schon
did not construct a design theory, then was (even) Simon not engaged in
theorising about design? Is Grounded Theory then about correlation (and
not really about theory)? And is anything under the label of "Social
Theory" (e.g. Marx, Adorno, Mead, Vygotsky) actually "theory" by this
definition?

I am convinced of the value of careful, consistent and formal
definitions in the advancement of scholarship, and I think your papers
and posts have been vital resources for design researchers towards this
end. But in the field of design, which sits astride so many traditional
disciplinary boundaries, is it problematic to appropriate a term that
has such a rich and useful history of use in a discipline that feeds
into design research (such as social theory)? Would we be better off
differentiating the epistemologically valid "theory" that you describe
as "formal theory" or "causal theory" or "epistemologically valid
theory"?

I think these are vital (and epidemic!) issues for design research, and
things that I need to understand better. Thanks very much for your time
and scholarship.

Kind regards,

Ben Matthews


Terry Love wrote:

As far as I can see, the most significant split in theory is that
between causal and correlatory approaches. This is especially
problematic when correlatory models of relationships between 'inputs'
and 'outputs' are carelessly or accidentally regarded as causal
representations.  This problem can be found in much the same form in
systems disciplines and in those disciplines that focus on stimuli and
responses or causal factors and consequences. The depth and consequence
of this problem are great because it is so extensive. The problem stems
from epistemological category confusion due in part to limitations in
data gathering techniques. There are many disciplines in which theory is
made about why people act in certain ways in particular circumstances
(e.g. history, economics, psychology, management, marketing, and design
research). The causal explanation, of agency and behaviour, lie in
understanding the physicality of how people function. Non-physical
theories (e.g. thinking, emotion, motivation, group behaviour,
attitudes, personality attributes) are epistemologically in a different
frame that cannot provide direct causal representation. These other
approaches, however, have the advantage that correlatory data is
relatively readily accessible. The difference in convenience, however,
might mask but does not avoid the difficulty that, due to their
epistemological and ontological status, they cannot provide casual
explanation.

This causal-correlation problem of theory making about human functioning
has led to many confusions being introduced into the literatures of
theory making.  Stepping back a bit, and going to Popper's main work on
theory making,  'Unended Quest' (Popper, 1976), he suggests that theory,
external observations and subjective perceptions lie in three
incommensurate 'worlds'. Put simply, Popper argues that it is not
possible to prove theory as true or false by observations or subjective
perceptions. Instead, he argues that theory is only validated in terms
of other tightly defined theories. This is now widely accepted in the
appropriate fields of philosophy (the same also applies in relation to
the other incommensurabilities, i.e. its not possible to prove
subjective perception by external observation or theory, and its not
possible to prove objective observation by subjective perception or
theory). In many theory literatures is found extensive evidence that it
has been assumed that correlatory evidence creates theory.  This is a
significant issue because it confuses distinctions between, concept,
correlation, theory, model, prototype, problem definition,
representation, internal imagogenic perception, feeling, emotion and a
host of other concepts.

The causal- correlatory split in theory making differentiates types of
theory and ways of building theory. A causal representation of a
situation is a result of deep understanding of how a situation functions
in terms of its physicality. This may involve concepts that are simply
place markers (e.g. the use of the concept of 'glucose tolerance factor'
to represent something that is yet unknown in theory representations of
the physiology of hypoglycemia). Its primary focus is, however, to
create theory that as representations has strong mapping onto the
physical causal processes.

Correlation-based representation contrasts with causally based theory in
many ways . The development of  correlation-based representations is via
the identification of statistically significant correlations between
'causal factors' and 'outcomes' to fix the constants in a mathematical
formula (e) that emulates the data. There are an infinite number of
formulae that can be used for this task and there is no requirement that
the formula (e) chosen map in any way onto the causal mechanisms. In
fact, they are often chosen for administrative convenience. If the
phenomena is relatively smooth and unchanging in its behaviour then
correlatory formula offer the basis for interpolating between data, and
for projecting a small way beyond data. In situations that are marked by
strong changes (such as many design situations) correlatory
representation of data offers little utility beyond simplifying the
presentation of the data. It is questionable as to whether this
justifies them being viewed as 'theory'.

Entirely a different problem, and needing more time and space than I
have is the situation in which simplified system models are based on
correlatory data. These models are commonplace in the literatures of
management, systems, education and learning. Characteristic of these
models is a lack of epistemological consistency (now increasingly
recognized as a serious weakness of systems approaches to modelling); a
foundation in correlatory rather than casual understanding of phenomena;
and a mode of representation that sacrifices correspondence with
underlying theory for simplified conceptualisation. That is, there has
been a shift from a theory representation to a reformulation as tool for
teaching or managing. In terms of theory development, this raises
concerns if the underlying theory becomes accidentally (or carelessly)
reformulated such that the teaching tool is regarded as the theory (the
unfortunate status of the teaching models of Kolb, Schon and other
researchers working in management and education).

_________________________________
Ben Matthews
Information Environments Program
University of Queensland
Brisbane Australia 4072
Ph +61 7 3365 8308

Top of Message | Previous Page | Permalink

JiscMail Tools


RSS Feeds and Sharing


Advanced Options


Archives

May 2024
April 2024
March 2024
February 2024
January 2024
December 2023
November 2023
October 2023
September 2023
August 2023
July 2023
June 2023
May 2023
April 2023
March 2023
February 2023
January 2023
December 2022
November 2022
October 2022
September 2022
August 2022
July 2022
June 2022
May 2022
April 2022
March 2022
February 2022
January 2022
December 2021
November 2021
October 2021
September 2021
August 2021
July 2021
June 2021
May 2021
April 2021
March 2021
February 2021
January 2021
December 2020
November 2020
October 2020
September 2020
August 2020
July 2020
June 2020
May 2020
April 2020
March 2020
February 2020
January 2020
December 2019
November 2019
October 2019
September 2019
August 2019
July 2019
June 2019
May 2019
April 2019
March 2019
February 2019
January 2019
December 2018
November 2018
October 2018
September 2018
August 2018
July 2018
June 2018
May 2018
April 2018
March 2018
February 2018
January 2018
December 2017
November 2017
October 2017
September 2017
August 2017
July 2017
June 2017
May 2017
April 2017
March 2017
February 2017
January 2017
December 2016
November 2016
October 2016
September 2016
August 2016
July 2016
June 2016
May 2016
April 2016
March 2016
February 2016
January 2016
December 2015
November 2015
October 2015
September 2015
August 2015
July 2015
June 2015
May 2015
April 2015
March 2015
February 2015
January 2015
December 2014
November 2014
October 2014
September 2014
August 2014
July 2014
June 2014
May 2014
April 2014
March 2014
February 2014
January 2014
December 2013
November 2013
October 2013
September 2013
August 2013
July 2013
June 2013
May 2013
April 2013
March 2013
February 2013
January 2013
December 2012
November 2012
October 2012
September 2012
August 2012
July 2012
June 2012
May 2012
April 2012
March 2012
February 2012
January 2012
December 2011
November 2011
October 2011
September 2011
August 2011
July 2011
June 2011
May 2011
April 2011
March 2011
February 2011
January 2011
December 2010
November 2010
October 2010
September 2010
August 2010
July 2010
June 2010
May 2010
April 2010
March 2010
February 2010
January 2010
December 2009
November 2009
October 2009
September 2009
August 2009
July 2009
June 2009
May 2009
April 2009
March 2009
February 2009
January 2009
December 2008
November 2008
October 2008
September 2008
August 2008
July 2008
June 2008
May 2008
April 2008
March 2008
February 2008
January 2008
December 2007
November 2007
October 2007
September 2007
August 2007
July 2007
June 2007
May 2007
April 2007
March 2007
February 2007
January 2007
2006
2005
2004
2003
2002
2001
2000
1999
1998


JiscMail is a Jisc service.

View our service policies at https://www.jiscmail.ac.uk/policyandsecurity/ and Jisc's privacy policy at https://www.jisc.ac.uk/website/privacy-notice

For help and support help@jisc.ac.uk

Secured by F-Secure Anti-Virus CataList Email List Search Powered by the LISTSERV Email List Manager