JiscMail Logo
Email discussion lists for the UK Education and Research communities

Help for EVIDENCE-BASED-HEALTH Archives


EVIDENCE-BASED-HEALTH Archives

EVIDENCE-BASED-HEALTH Archives


EVIDENCE-BASED-HEALTH@JISCMAIL.AC.UK


View:

Message:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Topic:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Author:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

Font:

Proportional Font

LISTSERV Archives

LISTSERV Archives

EVIDENCE-BASED-HEALTH Home

EVIDENCE-BASED-HEALTH Home

EVIDENCE-BASED-HEALTH  June 2000

EVIDENCE-BASED-HEALTH June 2000

Options

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Log In

Log In

Get Password

Get Password

Subject:

Re: Populations vs individuals (was Is it worth it?)

From:

"Martin Dawes" <[log in to unmask]>

Reply-To:

Martin Dawes

Date:

Fri, 23 Jun 2000 10:41:29 +0100

Content-Type:

text/plain

Parts/Attachments:

Parts/Attachments

text/plain (340 lines)

We had an interesting meeting yesterday talking about the extrapolation of
evidence to the individidual. I was reminded of the Cambridge study of
rotating 4 "effective" treatments of hypertension to see which one suited
which individual the best.

I see a difference in the population approach of NNT's and NNH's to the
strategic apporach to care in the individual. If one has a selection of
alternative therapies why don't we try them. This would avoid the problem of
"drug failure" which usually is interpreted as doctor failure when the 1st
drug is not succesful. I mean we talk about NNT's of 4 as great. yet that
means 3 individuals dont reach the arbitrary threshold.

How much more positive to suggest a program of 3 drugs so that the patient
can choose the one that suits them best! I don't know whether anyone has
done any research on how patients respond to this sort of approach. would be
an interesting trial??

martin

Dr Martin Dawes
Director Centre for Evidence Based Medicine
University of Oxford
Nuffield Department of Medicine
John Radcliffe Hospital
OXFORD OX3 9DU


----- Original Message -----
From: Mike McDowall <[log in to unmask]>
To: <[log in to unmask]>
Sent: Friday, June 23, 2000 9:53 AM
Subject: Populations vs individuals (was Is it worth it?)


> Both Ted Harding and Rod Jackson have denied the existence of a
> 'fundamental flaw' in statistics, and gone on to describe such a flaw
> beautifully (or in Ted's case, longitudinally). I agree with Rod, that
> statistics offer the best approaches we have at the moment (though
> I am worried about the expression 'appropriately weighted', I expect
> that would be used by some as an excuse for weighting with
> prejudice which I am sure is not what Rod would want). I am not
> saying that the flaw in statistics is fatal, merely a weakness. This
> weakness leads to Ted's 'paradoxical dilemma', which I hope we
> are all working to mitigate.
>
> The problem is exactly as Ted described. Analyses are wide open
> to different interpretation. Any technique is likely to be somewhat
> ambiguous, but I think we need to get closer to answering
> questions for individual patients before we can realise Lynda
> Jackson's dream (can I paraphrase that as 'treating patients
> according to their gene map, with supporting evidence' ?). The best
> we could manage at the moment would be to apply statistical
> analyses to results for similar patients. We would need to focus on
> a very small sample of patients if we are really going to look at
> (small groups of) genes. Using conventional statistics that would
> lead to great difficulty achieving sufficient sample size to provide
> reliable evidence - even if all the studies are properly designed,
> executed and analysed !
>
> We are far enough behind in amassing the evidence for the present
> generation of medical technology. Do we really want commercial
> interests to thrust unrealistic, unsupportable versions of Linda's
> dream (i.e. lacking the evidence) at patients while more responsible
> researchers cannot produce reliable evidence to refute
> unreasonable claims ? I know history repeats itself but we should
> also strive to learn from history, rather than sit back and let those
> commercial interests _make sure_ history repeats itself.
>
> In short, we are going to need better techniques for evaluating
> evidence. The sooner we can develop them, the better.
>
> Mike McDowall.
>
> P.S. I am particularly glad that Ted's alternative model of the law on
> drink driving is not used -
> > 11 o'clock on a Saturday night in the town centre, with inebriated
> > companions, and you get pushed up.
> Many of us take turns to act as taxis for our friends (and what
> about taxi drivers generally ?).
>
> > On 22-Jun-00 Mike McDowall wrote:
> > > Toby Lipman wrote :
> > >> we have
> > >> not adequately addressed the translation of population effects into
> > >> individual applicability.
> > >
> > > This is an issue I queried the list about some time ago (to
> > > deafening silence). We have developed models for prediction of
> > > outcome after stroke but are not comfortable that they can easily be
> > > mis-applied to individuals, where they are only really applicable to
> > > populations. I am afraid this is a fundamental flaw of statistics in
> > > general. When using Evidence from statistical analysis, you only
> > > have a probability (often not defined) that the evidence will be
> > > applicable in that particular case.
> > >
> > > So how will we fulfil Lynda Jackson's dream ?
> > >
> > > Yours sincerely,
> > >                 Mike McDowall (Mr.).
> >
> > This is an important issue, but I would dispute that it represents "a
> > fundamental flaw of statistics in general", at any rate where the
> > principles are concerned.
> >
> > There is almost always a difference between the characteristics
> > of a population and those of an individual, and in what is known
> > about these, and it leads to a paradoxical dilemma.
> >
> > I have preached the following on various occasions, and I would like
> > to give it an airing now.
> >
> > The Administrator and the Administratee have different (or potentially
> > different) "populations" in mind in questions of chance and
> > statistics. Their priorities (OK, utilities if you like) differ, and
> > their decisions and their beliefs (if any) can legitimately differ
> > radically in the face of the same apparent facts.
> >
> > A "medical" example (quotes used because simplistic and using
> > round-number pseudo-risks) concerns breast cancer screening.
> >
> > Suppose a test (e.g. mammography) has a 90% chance of giving the
> > correct answer (+ or -) if applied to any given subject (this
> > chance arising through random events in the operation of the
> > test procedure).
> >
> > Suppose that, amongst the population of women referred for
> > mammography, 1 in 20 have the disease (could be even less if GPs get
> > paranoid about failing to take proper care).
> >
> > Then, of those referred, the proportions with a positive test result
> > will be 9/200 who have the disease, and 19/200 who do not.
> >
> > The proportion of those with a positive result who have the disease is
> > 9/28, ~= 1/3. So a woman with a positive result probably does not have
> > the disease -- says the Administrator.
> >
> > The woman who gets her own personal positive result may well view the
> > matter differently: "They did a test which has 90% chance of getting
> > it right, and this test says I have the disease. So I probably have
> > it. The numbers of other women who have/don't have it shouldn't have
> > anything to do with whether I have it."
> >
> > Well, you can dispute the last sentence, since she did have her own
> > prior (historical) chance of getting it, if only one knew what it was.
> > One estimate of that could be the cross-sectional population
> > proportion (stratified appropriately by identifiable categories such
> > as family history, personal life factors, etc.), to the extent that
> > her history is "typical" -- or, in that splendidly deceptive word --
> > "representative" of the population in her stratum..
> >
> > Her own true chance mechanism is the historical line of her own
> > exposure to risk factors (including both ancestral events and
> > exposures during her own lifetime); and, if one knew these and the
> > risk mechanisms, then an estimate of her personal prior probability
> > could in principle be made. This one could call a "longitudinal risk
> > estimate" personalised for her.
> >
> > As far as she is aware, she has the _possibility_ of being one
> > of those for whom the longitudinal prior risk is high, and who
> > is in a position to tell her different? (I think Bayesians might
> > wish to intervene here and impose a higher-level prior on this
> > question, but that opens another dimension of discussion).
> >
> > So her last sentence could be interpreted as "why should my
> > longitudinal risk be the same as the cross-sectional risk of
> > the population of women 'like' me?"
> >
> > This might be the case if one could make an assumption (what
> > in mathematical terms might be called an "ergodic hypothesis")
> > that "long-term longitudinal risk equals large-population cross-
> > sectional risk". Whether that is legitimate or not is a matter
> > of fact according to the situation being considered, and the
> > known facts about the particular patient: does her personal
> > history "sample the risks" in the same proportions as the
> > instantaneous population "samples the risks"?
> >
> > Otherwise, we have a situation where the Administratee has
> > a different reference population for her chances than the
> > Administrator (the doctor). In that case, there is no reason
> > why they should agree about the "probability" that she has the
> > disease, since they are considering different things. (Of course,
> > doctors try to incorporate what they happen to know of the patient's
> > personal history, and thereby redress the balance between individual
> > and collective risk; but even then they may lack the information which
> > would help them to interpret what they know in terms of objective
> > risk).
> >
> > They also have different utilities. For the woman, having
> > the disease would be a personal disaster and very little else
> > would count: if it's at all likely, let's go all the way.
> >
> > The doctor falls between two stools: one the one hand, having
> > concern for the patient and to that extent sharing her
> > view; also, having his/her own back to cover and not wanting
> > to get a reputation for unduly overlooking real cases.
> > On the other hand, the doctor is the decision-maker for whether
> > to refer, so is the front-line custodian of NHS and Practice
> > resources, and will also feel that responsibility.
> >
> > And this gets worse as the Administrator gets more elevated:
> > a real NHS Administrator may say "we're wasting our resources
> > on 2/3 of the cases that this test shows as positive, not to
> > mention the 190/200 costly tests with negative results. Let's
> > tone down this screening program." This Administrator officially
> > can only look at the cross-sectional probability, otherwise
> > his job gets out of hand, since it is only cross-sectional
> > data that he can at all readily consider.
> >
> > However, the Administrator is also entitled to take "humane utilities"
> > into account: The function of the NHS is supposed to be to relieve
> > distress of medical origin, and it could be that ignoring a 1/3 chance
> > (cross-sectional) of breast cancer is politically unacceptable. But
> > that is a matter of negotiation.
> >
> > There is an analogous situation in the administration of criminal law.
> > There are very few crimes in the English statute book where the
> > criminality of others is proof of of your own (the only one that
> > springs to mind is Riotous Assembly -- mere presence at a riotous
> > assembly makes you guilty by definition). Otherwise, association with
> > criminals is not direct evidence of guilt, which has to be proved (in
> > criminal law) "beyond reasonable doubt" by evidence directly bearing
> > on the individual accused.
> >
> > Nevertheless, a particular individual who associates with criminals
> > has a personal ("longitudinal") probability of becoming involved with
> > them in a process leading up to a crime. If this probability could be
> > reliably evaluated (and came out to a near-certainty) then it could
> > legitimately lead to a conviction, even though there was no objective
> > (e.g. forensic, witness) evidence showing that X was indeed there and
> > indeed did this and that. Usually, the law of evidence inhibits this
> > line of proof because of the uncertainties usually associated with it
> > and in order to isolate the jury from prejudicial influence.
> >
> > The principle of "proof beyond reasonable doubt" is an administrative
> > filter whose purpose is to protect the innocent, even if this means
> > that a fair few guilty get off. The consequence is that people who are
> > "probably guilty" often do not get convicted.
> >
> > A good example of legal cross-sectional versus longitudinal evidence
> > would be the case of drink-driving. Merely being on the road at pub
> > closing-time on a Saturday night raises your cross-sectional
> > probability of being over the limit. In certain places at certain
> > times this could even rise to "much more probable than not". Yet your
> > longitudinal probability depends on your own drinking habits (from
> > zero for teetotallers to pretty high for some people) as well as on
> > what you happened to be doing that evening.
> >
> > Little of this gets into the law as it stands: You provide a sample,
> > breath or blood or urine, which is scientifically analysed and,
> > depending on the result, you are charged (and most likely convicted)
> > or not. (People do give evidence that they "only had one glass of
> > whisky so the breathalyser was probably wrong", but it doesn't usually
> > cut much ice).
> >
> > Yet there is enough error in the laboratory analysis to lead to
> > a fairly wide "grey area". This is allowed for, at present, by
> > subtracting a margin of error such that a positive outcome is
> > very unlikely unless the person really is guilty (in statistical
> > terms, this is a pure classical hypothesis test; and as it
> > happens this is the same logic as the mammography woman applied
> > to herself).
> >
> > However, could the circumstances of the case (e.g. when and where
> > driving and with whom) be used to resolve some cases in the grey area?
> > 11 o'clock on a Saturday night in the town centre, with inebriated
> > companions, and you get pushed up. 10 am on a Monday morning, alone
> > and miles from anywhere, and you get pushed down, maybe. But the law
> > ignores this. Nevertheless, the frequency of correct decision (viewed
> > cross-sectionally) could be improved by taking it into account. This
> > may lead to persistent injustice to one individual whose circumstances
> > are regularly unfortunate. The principle of "proof beyond reasonable
> > doubt" protects him. But it also allows others to escape justice.
> >
> > Other legal administrations (no names, no pack-drill) may take
> > the view that "we will get all the criminals we can, and never mind
> > the sufferings of the innocent". In the limit this can lead to
> > prevalent "guilt by association"; in the case of the sample taken from
> > the driver, this could mean that you _add_ the margin of error to the
> > lab result, just in case by chance it had come out low.
> >
> > Whichever way it's done, taking circumstances into account amounts to
> > adopting a Bayesian philosophy (with or without a numerical
> > calculation); and this is also basically the Administrator's approach
> > (though, as it happens, not that of administrators of the Criminal Law
> > who are Hypothesis testers; in Civil cases, however, it tends to get
> > much more "Bayesian" because of the "balance of probabilities"
> > approach).
> >
> > Well, this has gone on long enough, I dare say.
> >
> > In summary: there are probabilities ("cross-sectional") which apply to
> > populations, and probabilities ("longitudinal") which apply to
> > individuals. These may be similar or different, in any case depend on
> > different "reference sets", and one (usually the "cross-sectional")
> > may be known much better than the other (which may not be known at
> > all).
> >
> > Individuals and administrators (at different levels) may legitimately
> > vary in how they evaluate probabilities (indeed, they are in fact
> > looking at different information even if the data may look the same on
> > paper), and may (almost certainly will) have different criteria
> > (utilities) when it comes to determining what should be done.
> >
> > There is a distinction between a "hypothesis testing" philosophy
> > (which avoids incorporation of prior probability) and a "Bayesian"
> > philosophy (which tries to take it into account).
> >
> > In the case of the Administrator, who is looking at populations,
> > there is a reference "cross-sectional" population within which
> > "Bayesian prior frequencies" can be identified. Administrators
> > are [closet] Bayesians.
> >
> > In the case of the individual, the prior probability that should
> > really be taken into account depends on their "longitudinal"
> > history, and may be unknown: In that case, it can be argued
> > (and in fact I believe it is appropriate) that the prior-free
> > "hypothesis-testing" philosophy is appropriate.
> >
> > I believe this is an inevitable dilemma. To some extent it can
> > be alleviated if improved knowledge can lead to the two
> > sides having a wider basis of common ground in the information
> > they use. In any case, it is resolved in practice not "scientifically"
> > but by negotiation -- i.e. political means.
> >
> > Best wishes to all,
> > Ted.
> >
> > --------------------------------------------------------------------
> > E-Mail: (Ted Harding) <[log in to unmask]> Fax-to-email: +44
> > (0)870 284 7749 Date: 22-Jun-00
> > Time: 13:45:52 ------------------------------ XFMail
> > ------------------------------
>
>
>



%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%

Top of Message | Previous Page | Permalink

JiscMail Tools


RSS Feeds and Sharing


Advanced Options


Archives

April 2024
March 2024
February 2024
January 2024
December 2023
November 2023
October 2023
September 2023
August 2023
July 2023
June 2023
May 2023
April 2023
March 2023
February 2023
January 2023
December 2022
November 2022
October 2022
September 2022
August 2022
July 2022
June 2022
May 2022
April 2022
March 2022
February 2022
January 2022
December 2021
November 2021
October 2021
September 2021
August 2021
July 2021
June 2021
May 2021
April 2021
March 2021
February 2021
January 2021
December 2020
November 2020
October 2020
September 2020
August 2020
July 2020
June 2020
May 2020
April 2020
March 2020
February 2020
January 2020
December 2019
November 2019
October 2019
September 2019
August 2019
July 2019
June 2019
May 2019
April 2019
March 2019
February 2019
January 2019
December 2018
November 2018
October 2018
September 2018
August 2018
July 2018
June 2018
May 2018
April 2018
March 2018
February 2018
January 2018
December 2017
November 2017
October 2017
September 2017
August 2017
July 2017
June 2017
May 2017
April 2017
March 2017
February 2017
January 2017
December 2016
November 2016
October 2016
September 2016
August 2016
July 2016
June 2016
May 2016
April 2016
March 2016
February 2016
January 2016
December 2015
November 2015
October 2015
September 2015
August 2015
July 2015
June 2015
May 2015
April 2015
March 2015
February 2015
January 2015
December 2014
November 2014
October 2014
September 2014
August 2014
July 2014
June 2014
May 2014
April 2014
March 2014
February 2014
January 2014
December 2013
November 2013
October 2013
September 2013
August 2013
July 2013
June 2013
May 2013
April 2013
March 2013
February 2013
January 2013
December 2012
November 2012
October 2012
September 2012
August 2012
July 2012
June 2012
May 2012
April 2012
March 2012
February 2012
January 2012
December 2011
November 2011
October 2011
September 2011
August 2011
July 2011
June 2011
May 2011
April 2011
March 2011
February 2011
January 2011
December 2010
November 2010
October 2010
September 2010
August 2010
July 2010
June 2010
May 2010
April 2010
March 2010
February 2010
January 2010
December 2009
November 2009
October 2009
September 2009
August 2009
July 2009
June 2009
May 2009
April 2009
March 2009
February 2009
January 2009
December 2008
November 2008
October 2008
September 2008
August 2008
July 2008
June 2008
May 2008
April 2008
March 2008
February 2008
January 2008
December 2007
November 2007
October 2007
September 2007
August 2007
July 2007
June 2007
May 2007
April 2007
March 2007
February 2007
January 2007
December 2006
November 2006
October 2006
September 2006
August 2006
July 2006
June 2006
May 2006
April 2006
March 2006
February 2006
January 2006
December 2005
November 2005
October 2005
September 2005
August 2005
July 2005
June 2005
May 2005
April 2005
March 2005
February 2005
January 2005
December 2004
November 2004
October 2004
September 2004
August 2004
July 2004
June 2004
May 2004
April 2004
March 2004
February 2004
January 2004
December 2003
November 2003
October 2003
September 2003
August 2003
July 2003
June 2003
May 2003
April 2003
March 2003
February 2003
January 2003
December 2002
November 2002
October 2002
September 2002
August 2002
July 2002
June 2002
May 2002
April 2002
March 2002
February 2002
January 2002
December 2001
November 2001
October 2001
September 2001
August 2001
July 2001
June 2001
May 2001
April 2001
March 2001
February 2001
January 2001
December 2000
November 2000
October 2000
September 2000
August 2000
July 2000
June 2000
May 2000
April 2000
March 2000
February 2000
January 2000
December 1999
November 1999
October 1999
September 1999
August 1999
July 1999
June 1999
May 1999
April 1999
March 1999
February 1999
January 1999
December 1998
November 1998
October 1998
September 1998


JiscMail is a Jisc service.

View our service policies at https://www.jiscmail.ac.uk/policyandsecurity/ and Jisc's privacy policy at https://www.jisc.ac.uk/website/privacy-notice

For help and support help@jisc.ac.uk

Secured by F-Secure Anti-Virus CataList Email List Search Powered by the LISTSERV Email List Manager