JiscMail Logo
Email discussion lists for the UK Education and Research communities

Help for CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE Archives


CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE Archives

CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE Archives


CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE@JISCMAIL.AC.UK


View:

Message:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Topic:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Author:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

Font:

Monospaced Font

LISTSERV Archives

LISTSERV Archives

CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE Home

CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE Home

CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE  2006

CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE 2006

Options

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Log In

Log In

Get Password

Get Password

Subject:

[CSL]: [CTHEORY] 1000 Days of Theory: The City of God and the Gl obal City

From:

J Armitage <[log in to unmask]>

Reply-To:

Interdisciplinary academic study of Cyber Society <[log in to unmask]>

Date:

Fri, 6 Oct 2006 07:18:22 +0100

Content-Type:

text/plain

Parts/Attachments:

Parts/Attachments

text/plain (1039 lines)

From: [log in to unmask] [mailto:[log in to unmask]]
On Behalf Of Theory, Technology and Culture
Sent: 05 October 2006 20:29
To: [log in to unmask]
Subject: [CTHEORY] 1000 Days of Theory: The City of God and the Global City

_____________________________________________________________________
 CTHEORY: THEORY, TECHNOLOGY AND CULTURE VOL 29, NO 3
        *** Visit CTHEORY Online: http://www.ctheory.net ***

 1000 Days 043 05/10/2006 Editors: Arthur and Marilouise Kroker
 _____________________________________________________________________

                         *************************

                            1000 DAYS OF THEORY

                         *************************
 _____________________________________________________________________



 The City of God and the Global City
 ======================================


 ~Warren Magnusson~



 Augustine's famous distinction between the City of God and the City
 of Man has been re-worked in many ways. George Bush and Tony Blair
 certainly are not the only ones to think that we are caught up in a
 global struggle between good and evil, or to suppose that this
 transcendent struggle is immanent in everyday life. Nor is such
 thinking confined to the religiously minded. Since the eighteenth
 century, the great secular ideologists of modernity -- liberal and
 socialist, progressive and conservative, anarchist and statist,
 humanist and post-humanist -- have posed the most urgent problems
 within an Augustinian frame.[1] They tell us that there is an
 immanent, widely suppressed, but potentially transcendent "good,"
 faced with an omnipresent evil that can somehow be overcome or
 contained by those who commit themselves to the struggle against it.
 Apocalyptic in tone, universalistic in aspiration, reductionist in
 analysis, often violent in practice, this onto-theological politics
 gathers us all in from time to time. Those reared in the
 monotheistic cultures of Christianity, Judaism, and Islam may be
 particularly vulnerable to the appeal of such a politics, but there
 are many signs that people from other cultural backgrounds feel the
 pull of it as well.[2] In this context, it is particularly important
 to explore other ways of thinking, which are not so apocalyptic,
 universalistic, reductionist, or violent. There is no easy way of
 escaping Augustine's clutches, but his grip can be loosened.

 My suggestion is simple: that we take Augustine's central figure, the
 city, much more seriously as an analytical and political focus.
 Considered on its own terms -- that is, as the form of order implicit
 in urbanism as a way of life[3] -- the city transcends its place as a
 subordinate entity within a particular state. Even ordinary cities
 now have global reach, and the greatest of them function as command
 centres for the global economy.[4] Cities are key switching points
 for globalizing cultures and organizational centres for social,
 political, and religious movements. Moreover, cities are connected to
 one another in a way that gives form and meaning to the idea that we
 all now live in a single "global city," within which a global economy
 is organized and a global politics played out.[5] The city as the
 embodiment of urbanism as a way of life is not a merely local
 political entity. Nor can it be identified with the ancient ~polis~,
 which is the model for the modern republic. No particular city is
 self-contained. Nor is there a singular order to the city. A city is
 multiply networked and diversely ordered, internally and
 externally.[6] Most importantly, there is no sovereign centre to the
 urban way of life locally or globally. Forms of order (and hence
 centres of power) proliferate within and between cities. They do not
 remain stable. Whereas the state is characterized by sovereignty,
 cities are characterized by complicated practices of government and
 self-government, which overlap and modify one another. These
 practices work against any monopoly of authority. As such they can
 neither redeem us from evil nor lead us to glory. Neither human nor
 divine sovereignty is on offer. The global city may enable us to
 govern and express ourselves in various ways, but the terms are
 always limited by the freedom of others.[7]

 It is the absence of sovereignty within the city as city that has
 deflected the attention of political theorists from it. Political
 theorists have allowed others to conceptualize the city socially,
 culturally, and economically, but they themselves have failed to work
 out what the city is as a form of political order. In my view, that
 form is one that relates distinct practices of government and
 self-government to one another by means other than sovereignty. It is
 not that claims to sovereignty are unknown within the global city or
 particular cities. On the contrary, such claims are common, and
 sometimes seem productive. But, practices of government and
 self-government develop independently, and modify the impact of any
 effort to impose order by sovereign authority. Although we are
 trained to think of political authority as singular (that is, as
 something that flows from a sovereign centre), close attention to the
 reality of cities reveals something different. Multiple authorities
 are the rule, not the exception. Some of these authorities pretend
 not to be political, because that gives them more autonomy in
 relation to the ostensible sovereigns. (Business corporations are an
 obvious example, but there are many others.) Whatever the case, the
 field of government and self-government -- and hence the field of
 politics within the city, globally and locally -- is likely to be
 occupied by a variety of authorities that contend with one another,
 cooperate at times, seek to be autonomous, and work to impose their
 will in various ways. When cities work, in the sense that they
 provide reasonably congenial conditions of life for people, that is
 because of the ensemble of activities that these various authorities
 mediate, not because of the sovereignty that particular authorities
 purport to exercise. We know this, but we are too much under the
 spell of sovereignty to appreciate its significance. As a result, we
 exaggerate the political importance of the state and give too little
 attention to other political authorities like businesses, NGOs, and
 religious or other "movement" organizations that actually govern us
 in a variety of ways.

 Thus, to re-focus our political attention on the city is actually to
 open ourselves up to a re-examination of the conditions of
 possibility for civilized life. The argument in this article is
 neither for nor against state,[8] but it opposes a state-centric
 politics that belies the complexity of urban life and seduces us with
 notions of sovereign centre from which we can all be redeemed. The
 current "war on terror" (or, if you prefer, war on Islam) focuses on
 cities, but from the outside. Cities and the urban networks that
 connect them are recognized as the breeding grounds for the evils
 that Bush, Blair, and Bin Laden seek to eliminate. Cousins under the
 skin, the B & B & B warriors seek to redeem the city from without by
 forcing it to surrender to sovereign authority.[9] To think otherwise
 about our political possibilities is to move away from this moral
 drama and from the imaginary sovereignty that incites it. This is
 difficult, because we have so long been conditioned to think of
 politics in sovereigntist terms. My suggestion here is that we can
 use the figure of the city to work out the implications of a
 different ontology of the political, one that begins from the
 ubiquitous and proliferating practices of government and
 self-government -- the practices that make urban life possible --
 rather than from the sovereignty moves that are supposed to bring the
 political into being.[10] In doing this work, we have to draw on
 sources that make many people uncomfortable: in particular on the
 theorists who celebrate the magic of the market. In my view, these
 theorists mistake the implications of their own analysis, in that
 they neglect most of the practices that make civilized life possible
 in favour of the few that are associated with the market.
 Nonetheless, it is important to understand that the city can be
 conceived as a self-organizing system with no sovereign authority and
 no ultimate goal. That idea can inform a politics very different from
 the ones we associate with neo-conservatism and neo-liberalism.



 The City Becomes Global
 -----------------------

 The now familiar notions about global cities and the larger processes
 of globalization draw our attention to the way that cities work as
 connectors. Cities are the places where trading expeditions are
 organized. They are the sites at which information is gathered and
 exchanged, the places where the surplus is sent to be distributed and
 sold, and the locales where problems are identified and great
 projects are formulated. There are other kinds of places where these
 things happen, but the city is unique in its capacity to generate
 productive connections between people who are alien to one another.
 One need not be of the same religion or community or share the same
 allegiance or vision of the future to connect with others peacefully
 and productively. The city facilitates this, by bringing people of
 diverse backgrounds together, and giving them reasons to cooperate
 and live peaceably with one another. The city is a space of such
 opportunity that it calls us to put our differences aside for mutual
 advantage. Some of the opportunity at issue is economic, but there
 are other dimensions to it: cultural, religious, social, and
 political. To be "urbane" or "civilized" is to take difference in
 stride, react with tolerance and curiosity to alien customs, and to
 see the diversity of the city as an advantage. Every city is
 potentially global in that it welcomes people in and reaches out
 everywhere. In principle, a city is outside the order of sovereignty,
 in the sense that it transcends the realm or the state in which it is
 located and gathers people in, regardless of what the ostensibly
 "sovereign" authorities say they want. Urbanism as a way of life
 produces relationships that cannot easily be governed from without.
 Moreover, urbanism is fruitful in a way that makes authorities of all
 sorts dependent on its productivity. The productivity at issue is by
 no means only economic. City life enables new understandings, creates
 new connections, and produces new possibilities in every area of
 human endeavour.

 Max Weber thought that occidental cities were unique in the way that
 they worked as islands of freedom, in which the hold of the "higher"
 religious and secular authorities was loosened.[11] He exaggerated
 the distinctiveness of the Western experience. Urban life has its own
 logic, and everywhere it has had the effect of freeing people from
 certain constraints and giving them new opportunities for connection.
 When the Europeans burst out of their own corner of the world five
 hundred years ago, they created some new trading routes, but mostly
 they seized control of old routes and knit them together as part of a
 new system. They built new cities, but for the most part they took
 control of the older ones, and re-worked the urban system to new
 purposes. The long process of globalization was one in which
 autonomous urban systems were knit together and organized on a larger
 scale, thus facilitating more intense exploitation of the countryside
 and ultimately greater productivity. When the political economists of
 the eighteenth century tried to make sense of the emergent order,
 they focused on the exchanges that seemed to occur regardless of what
 the authorities might expect or require. These exchanges produced a
 civilized order more or less automatically. Everyone had an incentive
 to be peaceable in order to engage in exchange, and peaceable
 exchange was (for most people) more profitable than violent conquest.
 So, there was an immanent order, geared to free exchange and
 dependent on self-restraint or self-government, which tended to
 emerge naturally if it was not perverted by violence. If the violence
 of the European navigators and adventurers had been the hand-maiden
 of a new world order, the order itself was of a different character,
 based on free exchange between people (and peoples). Although it was
 rarely recognized as such, this cooperative order was the order of
 the city writ large.

 Most contemporary economists have an even narrower understanding of
 this order than Adam Smith did. They treat market exchanges in
 abstraction, and gloss over the fact that markets work to the
 advantage of the strong, the aggressive, the unscrupulous, and the
 self-interested. A market-mediated order is by no means ideal (as
 Marx made clear enough). That said, however, the economists are
 working with an important idea, namely that order can emerge from
 exchanges between people who have little in common with one another.
 In fact, the differences between people can be an incentive to
 exchanges of all sorts. If people see those differences as a reason
 to deal peaceably with one another, rather than to attack one
 another, then a peaceable order can emerge whether or not there is a
 powerful figure to enforce it. To understand this is to have a
 powerful insight, an insight on which the modern social sciences in
 general have built. Sociologists in particular have been keen to
 discern the properties of a naturally emergent order. By comparison
 with the economists, they are open to a subtler and more complicated
 understanding of that order. Of course, for the past century,
 critical work in sociology and political economy has tended to
 debunk theories that present the emergent order as benign or
 inevitable. The emphasis has been on exposing the structures of
 domination and plays of power that lie behind what seems like a
 natural order.[12] This critical work is useful, but it often
 obscures as much as it reveals. The best conventional sociologists
 and economists are not just ideologists. They have been trying to
 work out how a relatively benign and durable order can emerge despite
 the obvious structures of domination and plays of power. This is
 important work, but the neo-Augustinian political ontology on which
 most critics rely leaves little room for a story that fails to
 distinguish the good guys from the bad guys. The demand is for a
 clear moral ground on which we can stand and do our political work.
 As I shall attempt to explain in the next section, the ground
 demanded is the one offered by the state (however much the critics
 deny this).

 One of the problems that everyone has is that social scientific
 explanations tend to treat civilization as something that emerges
 either by violent imposition or by a process that occurs behind
 people's backs. The first sort of explanation is actually dependent
 on the second, in that stories of violent imposition presuppose
 processes that go on behind the backs of conquerors. The city is
 destroyed; the conqueror has to rebuild it; that can only happen if
 the conqueror submits to the creative energies of others. Social
 scientific accounts tend to obscure the fact that the emergent order
 is always established politically. In these accounts, politics is
 usually associated with the moment of violent imposition (or the
 ongoing practices of domination or the plays of power associated with
 domination) and not with the creativity (and the practices of
 peaceful exchange and cooperative effort) associated with building
 and sustaining a civilization. Thus, it is hard to see that the order
 at issue is always political. Critical work tends to treat politics
 as a scandal. To reveal that there are structures of domination or
 plays of power in a civilized order is to say that there is something
 bad there, generated by "politics". The remedy for this bad politics
 is always a good politics. An Augustinian political ontology always
 points in that direction. The alternative to this implicit
 Augustinianism is to put cheap moral judgements aside, and look more
 carefully at the various political practices that come into play when
 the problems of living together are posed. The problems emerge in
 everyday life. Everyone is involved in them in one way or another.
 Everyone has to be a politician. If a relatively benign -- or, at
 least, liveable -- order emerges, it will be the result of the
 political work that many, many people do. It is an open question what
 importance princes, presidents and prime ministers have in this
 context. Nevertheless, the lineaments of a benign order are
 fundamentally political.

 My point is that the city or civilization is a political construct
 that needs to be understood in those terms. The most creative
 political work is keyed to ubiquitous and proliferating practices of
 self-government. Individuals engage in these practices when they
 govern themselves, in the double sense of limiting themselves (so
 that their actions do not offend or otherwise impinge negatively on
 others) and taking charge of themselves. The latter part of the
 practice is celebrated by the ideologists of freedom.[13] The other
 part (self-limitation as opposed to self-expression or
 self-fulfillment) is what enables cities to function despite the fact
 that the nominal rulers are distant, ineffectual, or altogether
 absent. "Live and let live" really is the principle of urban life,
 for it is only on this principle that a multitude of strangers (with
 different customs and beliefs) can share the same space and go about
 their business in a relatively harmonious way. If Hobbes were right,
 cities would be impossible. What occurs at the level of the
 individual also occurs at the level of the group. Mutual
 accommodation is the rule, and it is this practice that actually
 enables particular groups to sustain distinct ways of life within the
 city. How this works is of particular interest to economists who have
 noticed how the incentive to trade generates markets governed by an
 ethic of peaceable exchange. For many economists, the market is a
 primordial fact, not requiring any particular explanation.
 Anthropological and historical evidence suggests to the contrary that
 it takes a lot of work -- political work -- to bring a market into
 being and sustain it.[14] This is true whether the market is a
 physical space or a more complex virtual space like the ones with
 which we are now familiar. Other practices also have to develop for
 civilized life to be sustained: rules of the road that enable
 undisturbed passage; practices that allow even the poor to find food,
 drink, and a place to sleep; rules about the keeping of animals and
 the disposal of wastes; codes of accommodation that relate to
 personal space, noise, and interpersonal address. The list is almost
 endless. It needs to be articulated only in part to reveal something
 else: namely, that the public services and facilities that we
 associate with modern life generally grew out of the practical
 necessities of living together in cities. We all need roads; we all
 need water; we have to dispose of our wastes somehow; we all want
 someone to turn to when other people break the rules. Government in
 the sense of the intense, intrusive activity in which the authorities
 are now engaged is something made necessary by life in cities, but it
 is nonetheless the tip of the iceberg: most of the activity that
 makes urban life possible occurs beneath the surface (as it were) in
 practices of self-government that develop whether or not the
 authorities are there to require them. The authorities generally take
 these practices for granted. So, (to change the analogy) government
 rests on a bedrock of self-government.

 The tendency among social scientists is to treat everyday practices
 of self-government as "social" or "cultural" and hence pre-political.
 This is a mistake. It obscures the political work that goes into the
 development and maintenance of these practices. Much of that work
 goes on in public, but it involves government officials only
 indirectly. People sort themselves out at bus-stops, on sidewalks, in
 cafes and restaurants, on waterways and in parks. These intimate
 practices of regulation and self-regulation involve plays of power,
 shows of authority, threats of violence, calls to solidarity, habits
 of deference, and challenges to the existing order: in short, they
 involve people in an everyday politics that vexes and threatens them
 from time to time, but that works surprisingly smoothly in most
 instances. We notice when things are going badly -- as in Baghdad or
 New Orleans recently -- because the norm is one of peaceful
 co-existence enabled by ubiquitous and proliferating practices of
 self-government.

 Narrow and ideological as it may be, Friedrich Hayek's work is
 interesting because it offers such a robust defence of the idea that
 a benign social order can emerge from these practices. One of his
 key claims is that the Great Society (as Adam Smith called it) is
 not an organization or ~taxis~ but a spontaneous order or ~cosmos~.
 This ~cosmos~ or spontaneous global order is a side-effect of things
 people have done for other purposes. No one can understand it as a
 whole, because it is not something that people have created
 consciously. It cannot be managed or planned by a central authority,
 because that authority can never comprehend it or adequately
 anticipate people's reactions to the situations in which they find
 themselves. Attempts to control the ~cosmos~ are counter-productive:
 we must live and let live.

      The Great Society arose through the discovery that men can live
      together in peace and mutually benefiting each other without
      agreeing on the particular aims which they severally pursue. The
      discovery that by substituting abstract rules of conduct for
      obligatory concrete ends made it possible to extend the order of
      peace beyond small groups pursuing the same ends, because it
      enabled each individual to gain from the skill and knowledge of
      others whom he need not even know and whose aims could be wholly
      different from his own.[15]

 In Hayek's account, the key principles of the Great Society are the
 ones that enable market exchange. This narrow reading is tendentious
 and ideological, however. A more generous reading enables us to see
 that civilization or ~cosmos~ or urbanity depends on other
 principles, like mutual recognition and respect, the search for
 consensus, concern for the common good, tolerance, generosity,
 charity, and humanity. As Hayek tells us, we can only identify the
 most valuable principles in retrospect, and we cannot predict what
 new principles of conduct will make the ~cosmos~ more robust or
 satisfying for people. Nonetheless, it is clear that the enabling
 principles of the emergent cosmopolitan order go far beyond the ones
 that Hayek himself identifies, and include many of the ones implicit
 in the everyday practices of self-government that enable cities to
 flourish. The Smithian Great Society and the Hayekian ~cosmos~ are
 actually the effects of everyday political initiatives.

 Hayek wanted to use constitutional measures to protect the
 spontaneous order of the human ~cosmos~ from statist initiatives. In
 a sense, he wanted to use the state against itself or (more
 accurately) to organize the state to forestall initiatives that would
 reshape the ~cosmos~ in accordance with some plan. Nevertheless, his
 own idea of what the ~cosmos~ is and should be informed the measures
 he envisaged, ones that would bind the state up and deploy it in a
 particular direction. Subsequent neo-liberal measures, both domestic
 and international, clearly follow from this Hayekian idea: a
 particular conception of the ~cosmos~ is to be embodied in legal
 principles that are beyond the control of particular states, popular
 movements, or local authorities. Those who abide by these principles
 are to be accepted as rights-bearing members of this liberal
 ~cosmos~. Others are to be treated as enemies. Thus, the current
 religious crusade against the enemies of neo-liberalism follows
 fairly directly from the effort to define the ~cosmos~ in advance and
 constitute it in a way that reflects a particular conception of human
 possibility. A more authentic commitment to the idea of a
 spontaneously ordered ~cosmos~ would not involve this return to a
 vengeful Augustinian moralism, nor would it lead to desperate efforts
 to forestall collective initiatives. Instead, it would problematize
 the moral/political centre that Hayek takes for granted: the modern
 state.



 The State Captures the Political Imagination
 --------------------------------------------

 Most analysts of the state seem to know little about the way it
 developed.[16] They focus on the concept of the state in abstraction
 from its practice, or on its practice in abstraction from the
 concept. To understand the concept, we have to go back to the late
 medieval era, and trace the emergence of ideas about the impersonal
 "state". We then have to understand how the state came to be
 associated with "sovereignty," a doctrine that took shape in the
 sixteenth and seventeenth centuries. Modern republican or liberal
 democratic theory, which evolved in the eighteenth century, was
 articulated on the assumption that the sovereign state was necessary
 for political order. Although this assumption certainly has been
 contested -- by nineteenth century anarchists and socialists, for
 instance -- it has been generally accepted since the early modern
 era. Indeed, it is so widely accepted now that most analysts fail to
 see any reason for making it explicit. The immediate effect of
 conjoining the ideal of democracy with the concept of the sovereign
 state (as happens in the contemporary political imaginary) is to give
 "politics" an obvious focus. If people are to resolve the big issues
 democratically, how can they not focus their attention on the venue
 that has been endowed with sovereign authority: the venue where the
 "ultimate" questions are decided? Surely any other politics must be
 peripheral. According to this logic, a politics focused on the great
 issues must be centred on the sovereign state, even if it proceeds
 through other institutions and practices and is oriented toward
 controlling what is outside the state.

 If we look at the practice of the state as it evolved in relation to
 cities, we begin to see something different: namely, that the
 politics that generated new activities occurred at the boundaries of
 urban self-government. This becomes clearer if we look at the history
 of the public services: education, transportation, policing, public
 health, and so on.[17] What we now take to be essential public
 activities -- sanitary disposal of liquid and solid wastes,
 suppression of fires, protection from criminal activity, maintenance
 and lighting of streets, etc. -- were not always present in cities.
 The great expansion of these services and facilities began in the
 nineteenth century and continued on into the twentieth. The
 taken-for-granted character of most of our public services and
 facilities is testimony to the fact that they developed out of
 people's efforts to deal with the practical problems of modern urban
 life. What to do about the filth of the streets? Animals running
 wild? People getting sick from the food sold in the markets? Kids
 roaming the streets and getting into trouble? Disease spreading out
 of control? Homeless people with nowhere to go? Workers without the
 education necessary for the jobs now available? Congestion that keeps
 people from getting to work? Foul-smelling air and polluted water?
 When people posed these questions to themselves, it was in the
 context of efforts to deal with problems by individual initiative or
 group action. At a certain point, someone said that this problem
 could only be solved if public authority were brought to bear, in the
 form of regulations to control the activities in question or taxation
 to raise the necessary revenues or direct administrative action on
 the part of the public authority in question. It was in this context
 also that many new public authorities were created, along with a
 variety of other institutions that defy easy characterization. On the
 ground, what we see now (or in any earlier era) is not the state on
 the one hand and society on the other, but a panoply of institutions
 rooted in people's efforts to deal with a variety of practical
 problems. These institutions are ~sui generis~. They conform to no
 single pattern. State activity in relation to these institutions is
 second-order: a matter of rationalizing the allocation of authority,
 clarifying jurisdictions, providing resources, specifying
 responsibilities, and so on. So, the politics that occurs at the
 level of the state is a second-order politics that only makes sense
 in relation to the first-order politics that occurs on the ground
 where urban services and facilities have to be developed.

 Most analysts assume that the second-order activities of the state
 are more significant because the state's authority is superior and
 its geographical reach greater. In fact, to take rationalization as
 one example, what occurs by way of the establishment of professional
 norms and standards may be at least as significant universally and be
 as much an effect of "indisputable authority" as anything that
 emanates from the state. The political struggles around these norms
 and standards are of great significance. Those struggles are rarely
 mediated by the state. Instead, the state (and other authorities)
 must adapt to these evolving standards. With respect to the familiar
 urban services, the basic form of the school, the hospital, the paved
 road, the sewerage system, and even the police force had to be worked
 out politically, but the venues in which that politics occurred were
 not legislative assemblies or ministerial cabinets (at least not for
 the most part). If we ask how the infrastructure of the modern city
 developed, we are led to many different sites of initiative,
 innovation, collaboration, competition, and political dispute, sites
 networked to one another in ways that do not correspond to the
 hierarchy of the state. So, the ontology of urban politics (the
 politics that generates the city as we know it) is quite different
 from the one presented by the familiar political ontology of the
 state. There is no obvious centre to urban politics, no Archimedean
 point from which the political universe can be moved, and no place
 whose political significance is guaranteed in advance. Where is the
 best place to act? That depends on the nature of one's concerns and
 on the particular configuration of forces in that time and place. We
 cannot know the answer in advance.

 An analyst might argue that what happens at the level of the city is
 only one aspect of what happens more generally, and that "high
 politics" occurs at a different level altogether. This is simply to
 repeat the statist mythology, however. If cities are globally
 networked -- as they evidently are -- then they are not "below"
 states. They are not contained "within" states, either. (This is most
 obviously the case with respect to places like New York City, but
 even small communities have a presence in the world that transcends
 their immediate physical boundaries, thanks to economic, social,
 cultural, and political links with people elsewhere.) The
 infrastructure of the modern state is essentially urban, and hence
 what is "of the state" is also "of the urban" and vice versa. To
 think the political through the urban rather than through the state
 is not to put the traditional questions of high politics aside. It is
 instead to ask how these questions appear in relation to all the
 other questions of urban life.[18]

 Is the imminent bird flu pandemic a matter of less concern than the
 proliferation of nuclear weapons, the adoption of terror tactics by
 political dissidents, the breakdown of order in major cities, the
 failure to control greenhouse gases, the immigration of the poor to
 the cities from the countryside, the lack of economic development in
 many parts of the world, the intensification of state and private
 security measures, or the general inadequacy of current mechanisms
 of democratic accountability? It would be hard to judge. It is
 clear, however, that each of these issues could well be considered a
 matter of high politics, if the human consequences of the issues
 concerned were our measure. The latter is not the measure suggested
 by the political ontology of the state, however. If something is
 crucial to the state, then it is a matter of high politics; if not,
 not. This trivializes the matter, by making any politics that eludes
 or transcends the state "low" by definition and insignificant by
 implication.

 The truth is that a God-figure is concealed in the conventional
 political ontology of the state. The notion of an "ultimate"
 authority or a "supreme" legislature is obviously borrowed from
 monotheistic understandings of the order of things. Because the state
 is imagined to have God-like powers, its significance is magnified,
 but in a way which is ultimately self-defeating. Although the state
 stands in place of God, it evidently is not God: it clearly lacks
 God-like powers. Because it cannot deliver on the sovereign power
 implicit in its own rationale, its ultimate authority seems hollow.
 Thus, we have people drifting away from the state and hence from
 politics as they conceive it, because the state/politics appears
 impotent. They may engage with the particular problems of urban life
 in other ways, inventing or supporting public services and facilities
 at one remove from the state or helping to develop regulatory
 practices that extend through the networks of everyday life. On the
 other hand, they may despair of the problems and reframe them in
 religious terms. This is the ground on which apocalyptic scenarios
 are laid out. Some of these scenarios bring the state back in, as the
 faithful are called to turn the supreme secular authority to their
 purposes.

 Many critiques of contemporary politics turn on a demand that we
 return to the old secular faith, a faith in the state as the ultimate
 redeemer. This demand is keyed to the idea that democratic politics
 is the field in which questions of right and wrong are appropriately
 joined. Democracy is supposed to overwhelm evil, and enable us to
 work out the good life for ourselves. The state is the imaginary
 centre at which our efforts come together, enabling us to deploy the
 good that we embody to the very limits of our power and authority. To
 lack faith in the state is to lack faith in ourselves as a sovereign
 people, a people capable of remaking its life in accordance with its
 own ideal of the good life. But, of course, such a faith is difficult
 to sustain. What is the alternative? I want to suggest that the
 alternative is in the various activities that make urban life more
 bearable. None of these activities is sovereign. There is no
 privileged place where we have to engage politically. Nonetheless,
 there are many places where we can act productively and where we have
 to be politically aware to be productive. The conventional political
 imaginary induces us to think that in turning from the state we are
 turning from politics. As a result, we know not what we do
 politically. It is not that people are turning away from politics,
 but that they have such a statist sense of what politics is that they
 have trouble understanding the fields of activity in front of them in
 political terms. This is profoundly disabling.

 Let us be clear about what is at stake. The question is not whether
 the state is withering away, morphing into a new shape, or returning
 to its old form. Nor is the question whether we should or should not
 act through the state. There is no reason to think that the state is
 about to disappear or that the venues it offers lack promise. The
 issue is how we are to conceive of our politics. Is our politics to
 be centred on the state or on the practices of self-government that
 enable cities to flourish?



 The Political Becomes Otherwise
 -------------------------------

 The idea that the political can be otherwise than state-centric is
 not new. In fact, it has been a constant theme in recent years, as
 various groups have focused on issues that others have tried to set
 outside politics proper. The disputed exclusions (women's issues and
 environmental issues, for example) were often justified on the
 grounds that the state lacked the authority or capacity to deal with
 the matters raised, matters that were properly within the ambit of
 society or culture or private business. So, to say that these
 exclusions had to be overcome (as feminists and environmentalists
 have done) was to say that politics had to transcend the state. This
 move was and is crucial because it enabled people to see that the
 line between the political and the non-political is not the same as
 the line between the state and society. One can be politically active
 in the state, in society, or in an indeterminate zone that seems as
 much one as the other. Is that not the meaning of what we call
 "social" movements, ones that defy the existing political limits, and
 establish spaces for political action that connect ordinary people
 with the wider world in innovative ways?[19] Once these spaces are
 claimed, don't new authorities arise, ones that have a powerful call
 on adherents and pose a challenge to the existing authorities?
 Although the more dramatic (or dangerous) movements catch our
 attention, there are many others that generate authorities quietly
 and establish important new spaces for politics in the process.

 Political authority takes many shapes, not only in the sense that
 Weber indicated in his famous system of classification, but also in
 the sense that authorities of different sorts emerge out of various
 practices of government and self-government and take forms quite
 particular to the purposes at hand. The authorities that deal with
 child abuse are not like the ones that deal with recycling. The
 individual who is called to take responsibility for child protection
 is not exactly the same individual who is enjoined to take
 responsibility for his or her own wastes. Different subjects or
 citizens are called into being by different practices, as are
 authorities with specific mandates and jurisdictions. Although there
 may be similarities between the various networks of government and
 self-government, there is never a complete identity. Thus, there is
 no single model for politics that carries from one field to the next.
 This is one of the main lessons of recent social movement politics,
 but it is also a lesson implicit in discussions of governmentality
 and globalization, which highlight the amorphousness of both
 phenomena. The space of the political is multiform, changeable, and
 ultimately so chaotic that it is not subject to sovereign control.
 Thus, the Augustinian imperative implicit in sovereigntist politics
 is a snare and a delusion.

 Most of the political authorities within contemporary networks of
 government and self-government actually make no pretence to
 sovereignty. They are just "local," in a geographic sense and
 otherwise. Although they claim regulatory authority and demand
 autonomy, they tend to concede that their authority and autonomy is
 not exclusive. Overlapping authorities are the norm. They interfere
 with one another less than they might, because they differentiate
 themselves from one another qualitatively. They see themselves as
 authorities of different types, and often co-exist with remarkable
 harmony. Even rivals can work out boundaries without too much
 difficulty when they lack the capacity to destroy one another. So,
 the universe of contemporary political authorities is highly
 differentiated. It cannot be mapped on the assumption that all
 political authority comes from a single centre, such as a
 constitution, a supreme legislature, or an imperial power. We can
 arrange the various authorities in a hierarchy (as
 sovereigntist/Augustinian thinking encourages us to do), but that
 will not tell us where the important centres of power are.

 The municipality is an especially important model in this context,
 because it is an integrative, but non-sovereign political authority.
 The fact that the municipality is the normative political form of the
 city (just as the state is the normative political form of the
 nation) is significant. It suggests that a self-governing city should
 not be a city-state that claims sovereignty but rather a municipality
 that enables self-government more generally, something it can do by
 facilitating citizen participation, connecting authorities of
 different sorts with one another, and stimulating innovation. If
 there is a model for global governance, it is to be found in the city
 and hence in the municipality, rather than in the nation-state. Not
 only is the municipal form of political organization more consonant
 with urbanism as a way of life -- and hence with the emergent global
 order -- but also it embodies practices that come out of our mundane
 requirements rather than demands for personal, national, or global
 salvation. The very modesty of the municipality is its virtue. In so
 far as it is not sovereign, it is not a God-figure, and its
 limitations are a constant reminder of the necessity of being modest
 in our objectives and practical in our orientation. There is no
 promise of transcendence in the municipality, although there is the
 possibility of acting together on matters of common concern. These
 matters may carry municipal leaders well beyond the bounds of their
 own municipality. This need not involve conflict with the state,
 since municipalities exist in a qualitatively different political
 space.[20] Of course, I am well aware of the claim -- backed by
 the superior courts in most countries -- that municipalities are just
 creatures of the state and hence prisoners within the political
 spaces of the state system. This claim is an inevitable consequence
 of the logic of state sovereignty. Current European discussions of
 the principle of subsidiarity replay this logic in a familiar way,
 reaffirming the hierarchy even in articulating a rationale for
 decentralization. Nonetheless, the idea of a municipality as a
 political entity of a different type remains with us, especially here
 in North America. A hundred years ago, it was common to talk of the
 municipality as a "joint-stock company" belonging to the people of
 the community concerned. (Was it enough to live in the community
 concerned or did one have to be a property-owner to be a full
 share-holder?) This conception pointed back toward the medieval
 origins of cities as centres of commerce and industry. On the other
 hand, there was a companion view that invoked the folk-moots of Saxon
 England or the warrior-assemblies of the Germans that Tacitus had
 described. Although the connection was rarely made at the time, these
 moots, assemblies, or meetings of the village, town, or parish were
 obviously similar to the ones that brought non-European peoples
 together in their villages, clans, or wider groupings. In the decades
 before the First World War, it was commonly argued that
 municipalities had to take the lead in dealing with the problems of
 urban-industrial life and that their strength lay in their capacity
 to organize people for purposes of local self-government. The
 presumption was that the state was at a distance, and that the
 practical problems of urban-industrial life required political
 authorities of a different type: more intimate, participatory, and
 immediately rooted. Although advocates of municipal autonomy usually
 deferred to the logic of state sovereignty (and so conceded that
 municipal authorities could only be lesser authorities within the
 order of the state, subject to the higher law of the state), there
 remained an element of defiance, which was reflected in ideas like
 municipal socialism. Even the idea that the municipality was a
 joint-stock company suggested that municipal governments were somehow
 outside the order of sovereignty.

 To think of the municipality as a political authority outside the
 order of sovereignty is to suggest that its roots are in the
 ubiquitous practices of local self-government rather than in the
 state as such. It is to pick up on Weber's conception of the city as
 a sphere of "non-legitimate domination": non-legitimate precisely in
 the sense that is outside the order of sovereignty. As Weber's phrase
 suggests, the order of the city is not necessarily benign, but the
 delusion of sovereigntist thinking is that we can free ourselves from
 domination by submitting to the absolute authority of the state. The
 alternative view is that political authority can be multiple in its
 forms and purposes, and that qualitatively different authorities can
 co-exist without any over-arching authority to regulate their
 relations. This is not anarchism. Quite the contrary, one might use
 the term polyarchy to describe it, had Robert Dahl not already used
 that term to refer to a pluralistic order of sovereignty.[21] The
 point is that the complexity of urbanism as a way of life is such
 that government must take various forms if it is to be effective, and
 that these various forms can co-exist with one another because they
 differ in their character as well as in their scale of operations.
 The notion of "side-by-side" authority is helpful in understanding
 this relation, but it can be misleading if it suggests that the
 authorities in question exist in comparable spaces. If authorities
 are qualitatively different from one another, they occupy spaces that
 are not strictly comparable. In Canada, aboriginal authorities have
 been claiming a space that is incommensurable with the space of the
 Canadian state. What that means in the end has still to be
 negotiated, but this much is clear: Canadian sovereignty does not
 limit the aboriginal right of self-government. How can that be?
 Aboriginal self-government exists in a different domain from the
 domain of the Canadian state, so that even if it touches on some of
 the same matters -- housing, education, social services -- it
 functions autonomously.[22] The analogy may be with the way that
 familial authority or corporate authority functions in a different
 domain from that of the state. A municipal authority, like an
 aboriginal authority, is more obviously political. To the extent that
 it asserts itself as an autonomous authority existing in a space of
 its own -- a space of local self-government -- it sets itself apart
 from the state and opens up political possibilities that cannot be
 contained within the order of the state or the state system. American
 municipalities that have committed themselves to the Kyoto Accord
 have recognized this, following the example of many other previous
 initiatives.[23]

 The political form appropriate to urbanism as a way of life is not
 the monopolistic state but a pluralistic order characterized by
 proliferating practices of local self-government. The municipality
 relates these practices to one another within a particular
 geographical territory, but it lacks the capacity to impose a
 sovereign order. Practices of local self-government spill over
 municipal boundaries, relate municipalities to one another and to
 authorities of other kinds, and divide the various municipalities
 from within. Municipalities exist within the domain of local
 self-government: they do not order it as sovereigns. Thus, the
 practices of non-sovereign government -- and hence polyarchal
 political authority in the proper sense -- are implicit in the
 relations within and between municipalities. The fact that
 municipalities have usually been overwhelmed by sovereign state
 authority is certainly important, but not as important as we usually
 imagine. Practices of local self-government are actually quite
 robust. They have to be: otherwise, cities could not exist. To see
 this is to see the possibilities of globalism in a new way. The fact
 that we cannot have a world-state or a federation of republics on the
 American model is not a matter for despair. On the contrary, it
 suggests that hopes for our future lie in the practices that generate
 urban order without resort to sovereignty. These are the practices
 that provide us with most security -- whatever the advocates of the
 gun may suggest to the contrary.



 Notes:
 ------

 [1] Compare William E. Connolly, _The Augustinian Imperative_,
 Newbury Park, CA: SAGE, 1993.

 [2] The ongoing conflict in Sri Lanka is one reminder of this, as is
 the legacy of the Pol Pot regime in Cambodia.

 [3] The phrase, "urbanism as a way of life," is from a famous 1938
 article by Louis Wirth, reprinted in his _On Cities and Social Life_,
 Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1964. Compare Henri Lefebvre,
 _The Urban Revolution_, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
 2003 (originally published published in French in 1970). Simon
 Parker, _Urban Theory and the Urban Experience: Encountering the
 City_, London: Routledge, 2004, offers a useful overview of the
 development of urban theory. See also Richard T. LeGates and Frederic
 Stout, eds., _The City Reader_, 3rd ed., London and New York:
 Routledge, 2003.

 [4] Compare Paul L. Knox and Peter J. Taylor, eds., _World Cities in
 a World-System_, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995, and
 Saskia Sassen, _The Global City: New York, London, Tokyo_, rev. ed.,
 Princeton NJ: Princeton University Press, 2001.

 [5] Marshall McLuhan's concept of the "global village" anticipates
 this idea: _Understanding Media: The Extensions of Man_ (New York:
 Signet, 1964). I develop the idea in a way pertinent to this
 discussion in "Social Movements and the Global City," _Millennium:
 Journal of International Studies_, XXIII:3 (Winter 1994), 621-45, and
 "Politicizing the Global City," _Democracy, Citizenship, and the
 Global City_, ed. Engin Isin, (London: Routledge, 2000), 289-306.

 [6] Manuel Castells, _The Rise of the Network Society_, Oxford:
 Blackwell, 1996.

 [7] Compare Hannah Arendt, _Between Past and Future_, London: Faber,
 1961.

 [8] Nor is it an argument for reducing the scale of the state to that
 of the city. A city-state is not inherently superior to a
 nation-state.

 [9] Compare Bruce B. Lawrence, ed., _Messages to the World: The
 Statements of Osama Bin Laden_, London: Verso, 2005, and Michael
 Ignatieff, ed., _American Exceptionalism and Human Rights_,
 Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2005.

 [10] Most recent accounts, such as Agamben's, follow Carl Schmitt in
 this regard. They confuse politics with a certain concept of it,
 produced by sovereignty. Compare Giorgio Agamben, _Homo Sacer:
 Sovereign Power and Bare Life_, Stanford: Stanford University Press,
 1998, and Chantal Mouffe, ed., _The Challenge of Carl Schmitt_,
 London: Verso 1999.

 [11] Max Weber, _Economy and Society_, Berkeley: University of
 California Press, 1978, vol. 2, ch. 16.

 [12] For example, see Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri. _Empire_,
 Cambridge MA: Harvard University Press, 2000.

 [13] Compare Nikolas Rose, _Powers of Freedom: Reframing Political
 Thought_, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.

 [14] Karl Polanyi, _The Great Transformation_, New York: Rinehart &
 Co, 1944.

 [15] Friedrich A. Hayek, _Law, Legislation and Liberty_, London:
 Routledge, 1998, vol. 2, p. 109. Compare _The Constitution of
 Liberty_, Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1960.

 [16] See, however, Jens Bartelson, _A Genealogy of Sovereignty_,
 Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995, and _The Critique of the
 State_, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2001.

 [17] See especially Jon C. Teaford, _The Unheralded Triumph: City
 Government in America, 1870-1900_, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins
 University Press, 1984.

 [18] The difficulties that urbanists have had with these issues
 post-9/11 are reflected in two symposia: _Urban Affairs Review_ 37:3
 (2002), pp. 460-67, and _International Journal of Urban and Regional
 Research_ 27.3 (2003), pp. 649-98. See also Hank V. Savitch, "Does
 9-11 portend a new paradigm for cities?" _Urban Affairs Review_
 39.1(2003), pp. 103-27. In my view, most urbanists still think the
 political in statist terms, despite their commitment to urban
 analysis. Compare William Finnegan, "The Terrorist Beat: How is the
 N.Y.P.D. defending the city?" ~The New Yorker~, 25 July 2005.
 Finnegan's analysis makes clear that the actual struggle to deal with
 terrorist threats to New York City is led by the municipal police
 department, a department that necessarily thinks locally and acts
 globally.

 [19] Compare William K. Carroll, ed., _Organizing Dissent:
 Contemporary Social Movements in Theory and Practice_, 2nd ed.,
 Toronto: Garamond Press, 1997.

 [20] I have explored the implications of this idea in a trio of
 recent articles focused on the Canadian situation: "Are
 Municipalities Creatures of the Provinces?" _Journal of Canadian
 Studies_, 39:2 (Spring 2005), 5-29, "Urbanism, cities and local
 self-government," _Canadian Public Administration_, 48:1 (Spring
 2005), 96-123, and "Protecting the Right of Local Self-Government,"
 _Canadian Journal of Political Science_, 38:4 (December 2005), 1-26.

 [21] Robert A. Dahl, _Polyarchy; Participation and Opposition_, New
 Haven: Yale University Press, 1971.

 [22] Compare James Tully, _Strange Multiplicity: Constitutionalism in
 the Age of Diversity_, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995.

 [23] See http://www.ci.seattle.wa.us/mayor/climate/ for the US Mayors
 Climate Protection Agreement of 13 June 2005. I have discussed a
 number of the earlier initiatives in _The Search for Political Space:
 Globalization, Social Movements and the Urban Political Experience_,
 Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1996, ch. 11.

 --------------------
 Warren Magnusson teaches urban politics and political theory at the
 the University of Victoria, Canada. Among his books are _The Search
 for Political Space_ (1996) and _A Political Space: Reading the
 Global through Cloyoquot Sound_ (2003), with Karena Shaw.

 _____________________________________________________________________

 *
 * CTHEORY is an international peer-reviewed journal of theory,
 * technology and culture. Articles, interviews, and key book
 * reviews in contemporary discourse are published weekly as
 * well as theorisations of major "event-scenes" in the
 * mediascape.
 *
 * Editors: Arthur and Marilouise Kroker
 *
 * Editorial Board: Jean Baudrillard (Paris), Paul Virilio (Paris),
 * Bruce Sterling (Austin), R.U. Sirius (San Francisco), Siegfried
 * Zielinski (Koeln), Stelarc (Melbourne), Richard Kadrey (San
 * Francisco), DJ Spooky [Paul D. Miller] (NYC), Timothy Murray
 * (Ithaca/Cornell), Lynn Hershman Leeson (San Francisco), Stephen
 * Pfohl (Boston), Andrew Ross (NYC), David Cook (Toronto), Ralph
 * Melcher (Sante Fe), Shannon Bell (Toronto), Gad Horowitz
 * (Toronto), Andrew Wernick (Peterborough).
 *
 * In Memory: Kathy Acker
 *
 * Editorial Assistant: Ted Hiebert
 * WWW Design & Technical Advisor: Spencer Saunders (CTHEORY.NET)
 * WWW Engineer Emeritus: Carl Steadman

 _____________________________________________________________________

                To view CTHEORY online please visit:
                      http://www.ctheory.net/

            To view CTHEORY MULTIMEDIA online please visit:
                 http://ctheorymultimedia.cornell.edu/

 _____________________________________________________________________

 * CTHEORY includes:
 *
 * 1. Electronic reviews of key books in contemporary theory.
 *
 * 2. Electronic articles on theory, technology and culture.
 *
 * 3. Event-scenes in politics, culture and the mediascape.
 *
 * 4. Interviews with significant theorists, artists, and writers.
 *
 * 5. Multimedia theme issues and projects.
 *
 *
 * The Editors would like the thank the University of Victoria for
 * financial and intellectual support of CTheory. In particular, the
 * Editors would like to thank the Dean of Social Sciences, Dr. C.
 * Peter Keller, the Dean of Engineering, Dr. D. Michael Miller and
 * Dr. Jon Muzio, Department of Computer Science.
 *
 _____________________________________________________________________
 *
 * (C) Copyright Information:
 *
 * All articles published in this journal are protected by
 * copyright, which covers the exclusive rights to reproduce and
 * distribute the article. No material published in this journal
 * may be translated, reproduced, photographed or stored on
 * microfilm, in electronic databases, video disks, etc., without
 * first obtaining written permission from CTheory.
 * Email [log in to unmask] for more information.
 *
 _____________________________________________________________________
 *
 * Mailing address: CTHEORY, University of Victoria, PO Box 3050,
 * Victoria, BC, Canada, V8W 3P5.
 *
 * Full text and microform versions are available from UMI, Ann Arbor,
 * Michigan; and Canadian Periodical Index/Gale Canada, Toronto.
 *
 * Indexed in: International Political Science Abstracts/
 * Documentation politique international; Sociological Abstract
 * Inc.; Advance Bibliography of Contents: Political Science and
 * Government; Canadian Periodical Index; Film and Literature Index.
 *
 _____________________________________________________________________

_______________________________________________
ctheory mailing list
[log in to unmask]
https://lists.uvic.ca/mailman/listinfo/ctheory

--
This message has been scanned for viruses and dangerous
content by the NorMAN MailScanner Service and is believed
to be clean.

The NorMAN MailScanner Service is operated by Information
Systems and Services, Newcastle University.


====
This e-mail is intended solely for the addressee. It may contain private and
confidential information. If you are not the intended addressee, please take
no action based on it nor show a copy to anyone. Please reply to this e-mail
to highlight the error. You should also be aware that all electronic mail
from, to, or within Northumbria University may be the subject of a request
under the Freedom of Information Act 2000 and related legislation, and
therefore may be required to be disclosed to third parties.
This e-mail and attachments have been scanned for viruses prior to leaving
Northumbria University. Northumbria University will not be liable for any
losses as a result of any viruses being passed on.

************************************************************************************
Distributed through Cyber-Society-Live [CSL]: CSL is a moderated discussion
list made up of people who are interested in the interdisciplinary academic
study of Cyber Society in all its manifestations.To join the list please visit:
http://www.jiscmail.ac.uk/lists/cyber-society-live.html
*************************************************************************************

Top of Message | Previous Page | Permalink

JiscMail Tools


RSS Feeds and Sharing


Advanced Options


Archives

May 2024
April 2024
March 2024
February 2024
January 2024
December 2023
November 2023
October 2023
September 2023
August 2023
July 2023
June 2023
May 2023
April 2023
March 2023
February 2023
January 2023
December 2022
November 2022
October 2022
September 2022
August 2022
June 2022
May 2022
March 2022
February 2022
October 2021
July 2021
June 2021
April 2021
March 2021
February 2021
January 2021
December 2020
November 2020
October 2020
September 2020
July 2020
June 2020
May 2020
April 2020
February 2020
January 2020
December 2019
November 2019
October 2019
September 2019
August 2019
July 2019
June 2019
May 2019
March 2019
February 2019
January 2019
December 2018
November 2018
October 2018
September 2018
August 2018
July 2018
June 2018
May 2018
April 2018
March 2018
February 2018
January 2018
December 2017
November 2017
October 2017
September 2017
August 2017
July 2017
June 2017
May 2017
April 2017
March 2017
January 2017
December 2016
November 2016
October 2016
September 2016
August 2016
June 2016
May 2016
April 2016
March 2016
February 2016
January 2016
December 2015
November 2015
October 2015
September 2015
August 2015
July 2015
June 2015
May 2015
April 2015
March 2015
February 2015
January 2015
December 2014
November 2014
October 2014
September 2014
August 2014
June 2014
May 2014
April 2014
March 2014
February 2014
January 2014
December 2013
November 2013
October 2013
September 2013
August 2013
July 2013
June 2013
May 2013
April 2013
March 2013
February 2013
January 2013
December 2012
November 2012
October 2012
September 2012
August 2012
July 2012
June 2012
May 2012
April 2012
March 2012
February 2012
January 2012
December 2011
November 2011
October 2011
September 2011
July 2011
June 2011
May 2011
April 2011
March 2011
February 2011
January 2011
December 2010
November 2010
October 2010
September 2010
August 2010
July 2010
June 2010
May 2010
April 2010
March 2010
February 2010
January 2010
December 2009
November 2009
October 2009
September 2009
July 2009
June 2009
May 2009
April 2009
March 2009
February 2009
January 2009
December 2008
November 2008
October 2008
September 2008
June 2008
May 2008
April 2008
March 2008
February 2008
January 2008
December 2007
November 2007
October 2007
September 2007
June 2007
May 2007
April 2007
March 2007
February 2007
January 2007
2006
2005
2004
2003
2002
2001
2000


JiscMail is a Jisc service.

View our service policies at https://www.jiscmail.ac.uk/policyandsecurity/ and Jisc's privacy policy at https://www.jisc.ac.uk/website/privacy-notice

For help and support help@jisc.ac.uk

Secured by F-Secure Anti-Virus CataList Email List Search Powered by the LISTSERV Email List Manager