JiscMail Logo
Email discussion lists for the UK Education and Research communities

Help for CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE Archives


CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE Archives

CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE Archives


CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE@JISCMAIL.AC.UK


View:

Message:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Topic:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

By Author:

[

First

|

Previous

|

Next

|

Last

]

Font:

Proportional Font

LISTSERV Archives

LISTSERV Archives

CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE Home

CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE Home

CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE  2005

CYBER-SOCIETY-LIVE 2005

Options

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Subscribe or Unsubscribe

Log In

Log In

Get Password

Get Password

Subject:

[CSL]: [CTHEORY] Article 165 - Biophilosophy for the 21st Century

From:

J Armitage <[log in to unmask]>

Reply-To:

Interdisciplinary academic study of Cyber Society <[log in to unmask]>

Date:

Wed, 7 Sep 2005 07:27:14 +0100

Content-Type:

text/plain

Parts/Attachments:

Parts/Attachments

text/plain (748 lines)

From: [log in to unmask]
To: [log in to unmask]
Sent: 06/09/2005 23:31
Subject: [CTHEORY] Article 165 - Biophilosophy for the 21st Century

_____________________________________________________________________
 CTHEORY          THEORY, TECHNOLOGY AND CULTURE        VOL 28, NO 3
        *** Visit CTHEORY Online: http://www.ctheory.net ***

 Article 165     06/09/2005     Editors: Arthur and Marilouise Kroker
 _____________________________________________________________________

                         *************************

                            1000 DAYS OF THEORY

                         *************************
 _____________________________________________________________________



 Biophilosophy for the 21st Century
 ======================================================


 ~Eugene Thacker~



 Soul-Meat-Pattern
 -----------------

 There have only ever been three approaches to thinking about life:
 SOUL, MEAT, and PATTERN. Within this trinity is everything deemed to
 be animate, living, and vital. 'Soul' is not just the Scholastic,
 theological, personal soul, but the Aristotelian principle of life
 (~psyche~), the principle of its organization. The vegetative soul of
 plants, the animate and sensate soul of animals, and the rational
 soul of human beings. The hierarchy of souls is not unlike the Great
 Chain of Being, a biological theology of divide-and-hierarchize. By
 contrast, 'meat' is brute matter, unthinking mechanism, the clockwork
 organism, the ~bete machine~ described by Descartes -- animal or
 machine, it makes no difference. Mechanism is, in a sense, a thinking
 about life as meat, and meat as lifeless (the life that is lifeless
 is meat or machine). Finally, distinct from 'soul' and 'meat' is a
 third approach, that of 'pattern.' It would seem that the emphasis on
 pattern is a distinctly postmodern phenomenon, the terrain of
 cybernetics, information theory, self-organization. But this is only
 part of the story. Again, Aristotle the biologist equates form
 (~eidos~) and 'soul' as the distinguishing mark between the plant,
 the animal, and the human; it is in their mode of organization, how
 they self-actualize in time ('if it moves, it's alive'). Yet,
 Aristotle is linked to contemporary self-organization research in
 that neither can explain how organization occurs, other than to
 reiterate that the whole is more than the sum of its parts.

 Thus, 'soul,' 'meat,' and 'pattern' form a trinity. The trinity is
 also a triptych: soul in the center, meat on the right-hand side, and
 on the left, pattern. An image of thought that continuously switches,
 swaps, displaces, and replaces the place-holder that defines life:
 from ~psyche~ to mechanism and animal electricity to the 'gemmules'
 and 'pangens' to DNA and the 'code of life.' However, these three
 approaches do not form a periodization, with Aristotle's ~psyche~
 followed by Descartes' clockwork body followed by the genetic code.
 Instead, as a trinity-triptych, they form a kind of portrait, a face,
 a faciality, a field of black holes and white walls, within which and
 upon which is often written: 'life is that whose essence can be
 deduced and yet whose essence escapes all deduction.'
 Soul-meat-pattern. Each of these posits a central, universal,
 external principle of organization that culminates in the living, the
 organism, a life-force. We can simply refer to this as the principle
 of life, the central concept that structures a whole field of
 investigation. Each approach differs in its place-holders, but there
 continues to be a transcendental locus that minimally guarantees a
 description of life, something that enables one to point and say
 'over there...' (or perhaps, 'it's alive...alive!' or again, 'shoot
 anything with more than two legs!'). In positing such principles of
 organization, the soul-meat-pattern triptych also articulates
 boundaries: living-nonliving, organic-inorganic, animate-inanimate,
 but also animal-machine, human-animal, human-savage, species, races,
 populations, genomes...We can refer to this practice as boundaries of
 articulation. Together, the principle of life and the boundaries of
 articulation are the two methods through which the West has
 ceaselessly reinvented its thinking about life.



 Extrinsic life
 --------------

 There is an inward-turning and an outward-turning aspect of this
 thinking. The inward-turning divides, orders, and interrelates
 species and types; the outward-turning manages boundaries and
 positions the living against the nonliving, making possible an
 instrumentality, a standing-reserve. The inward-turning aspect is
 metabolic, in that it processes, filters, and differentiates itself
 internally; it is the breakdown and production of biomolecules, the
 organization of the organs, the genesis of species and races. The
 outward-turning aspect is immunologic, for it manages boundaries,
 exchanges, passages; it is the self-nonself distinction, the organism
 exchanging with its environment, sensing its milieu, the individual
 body living in proximity to other bodies. Nevertheless, there is
 always something that complicates both aspects. The inward-turning
 aspect is just fine until the outward-turning aspect loses its grip
 on things. An example is epidemics. An epidemic cannot be limited to
 the individual organism, for its very nature is to pass between
 organisms, and increasingly, to pass across species borders (and
 national borders). What is the unit of analysis for an epidemic?
 Likewise, the outward-turning aspect is able to manage boundaries
 without problem until the inward-turning aspect is discovered to be
 an illusion. For instance, if the outward-turning aspect is that
 which posits the individual organism as distinct from its
 environment, therefore enabling an instrumental relationship, a
 standing reserve, what then is the inward-turning aspect? We would
 assume it is the whole spectrum of understanding about that organism
 -- its biological, physiological, cognitive processes. But isn't each
 of these really a nested, outward-turning aspect in itself? What are
 the systems, networks, and pathways of the organism if not nested
 layers of the outward-turning aspect? The inward-turning and
 outward-turning aspects thus complicate each other ceaselessly, and
 it is therefore not inaccurate to describe their relationship, as
 Deleuze does, as one of folding (in-folding, out-folding, an
 embryology having nothing to do with 'development').

 Soul-meat-pattern. Again, this is not a ~telos~, as if to imply that
 genetic and information technologies are the most advanced mode of
 inward- and outward-turning. Yet, in a time of networks, swarms, and
 multitudes, it would seem that the third approach -- that of
 'pattern' -- is today dominant in the life sciences (genetics,
 genomics), health care (biotech industry), technology (a-life, AI,
 networks), war (bioterror, emerging epidemics) and even alternative
 scientific viewpoints (biocomplexity, emergence) [1]. A new, vital
 pattern pervades systems of all kinds -- global economies, social
 systems, immigration patterns, information exchanges, mobile and
 wireless communications, and so forth. Despite this, have we rid
 ourselves of the divide-and-hierarchize mentality of thinking about
 life? Is 'pattern' simply the new 'soul'? Traditionally, these
 questions about the principle of life come under the domain of the
 philosophy of biology. But what would it mean to invert the
 philosophy of biology? What would it mean to invert this thinking
 (soul-meat-pattern) and this dualistic method (principles of life,
 boundaries of articulation), and consider instead a biophilosophy?
 Perhaps it is precisely 'life itself' that is the problem, not the
 aim or the goal. Instead of considering the intrinsic properties of
 life, what about considering life as extrinsic, as always going
 outside of itself? Instead of centering life (an essence, an
 organizing principle), what about considering life at the
 peripheries? Extrinsic life, a life always going outside of itself,
 peripheral life...



 Biophilosophy vs. Philosophy of Biology
 ---------------------------------------

 What, then, is biophilosophy? To begin with, biophilosophy is not the
 same as the philosophy of biology. What is usually referred to as the
 philosophy of biology has both a syntagmatic and a paradigmatic side
 to it, a horizontal and vertical dimension to it. The horizontal
 dimension is the elucidation of universal characteristics of the
 organism which are perceived to be part of its essence or principle
 of organization (growth and decay, reproduction and development,
 evolutionary adaptation). The vertical dimension is the development
 of this thinking historically in Western thought, from Aristotle, to
 natural history, to Darwinian evolution, to the new synthesis in
 genetics and biochemistry. In general, the philosophy of biology
 highlights and extends the philosophical dimensions of biological
 knowledge. Issues pertaining to evolution, biological determinism,
 dualism, mechanism, and teleology may be considered in the context of
 the life sciences such as comparative anatomy, physiology, genetics,
 biochemistry, embryology, germ theory, developmental systems theory.
 The philosophy of biology informs the three approaches to thinking
 about life mentioned above: soul-meat-pattern. The philosophy of
 biology also undertakes the twofold method of identifying a principle
 of life and boundaries of articulation. It can be understood as an
 attempt to pose the question 'is the living different from the
 non-living?' -- an ontological question -- in the context of another
 question, 'is the study of the living (biology) different from other
 fields of study?' -- an epistemological question.

 Is biophilosophy simply the opposite of the philosophy of biology?
 Not quite. Biophilosophy is certainly a critique of the triptych of
 philosophy of biology. But it is also a way of moving through the
 soul-meat-pattern approach, while taking with it the radicality of
 the ontological questions that are posed, and which often get reduced
 to epistemological concerns over classification. Whereas the
 philosophy of biology is concerned with articulating a concept of
 'life' that would describe the essence of life, biophilosophy is
 concerned with articulating those things that ceaselessly transform
 life. For biophilosophy, life = multiplicity. Whereas the philosophy
 of biology proceeds by the derivation of universal characteristics
 for all life, biophilosophy proceeds by drawing out the network of
 relations that always take the living outside itself. An extrinsic
 diagram as opposed to intrinsic characteristics. Whereas the
 philosophy of biology (especially in the 20th century) is
 increasingly concerned with reducing life to number (from mechanism
 to genetics), biophilosophy sees a different kind of number, one that
 runs through life (a combinatoric, proliferating number, the number
 of graphs, groups, and sets). Whereas the philosophy of biology
 renews mechanism in order to purge itself of all vitalism ('vitalism'
 is one of the curse words of biology...), biophilosophy renews
 vitalism in order to purge it of all theology (and in this sense
 number is vitalistic).



 'A life' not A-life
 -------------------

 The difficulty with the philosophy of biology -- as with nearly all
 philosophical thinking of 'the animal' -- is to resist the
 anthropomorphism of our thinking about life. The approach of the
 philosophy of biology, the approach of soul-meat-pattern, centers and
 raises up the concept of the human so that it is not only isomorphic
 with life, but so that it may rise above life ('life itself' as the
 pinnacle and 'mere life' as the base or foundation). This has a
 number of effects on our thinking about life, for it simultaneously
 places the human at the top of the Great Chain while also reserving a
 qualitatively distinct, non-animal place for the human. This is the
 tired drama of the human, at once partaking of the animal, natural,
 biological world, and yet incessantly striving above and beyond it,
 producing abstract knowledge-systems, constructing world and life,
 aspiring for the spiritual (recall Heidegger's thesis concerning
 animality: the stone is worldless, the animal is poor-in-world, and
 the human is world-building). It is a drama that is by turns tragic
 and absurdist. Contemporary bio-art practices can be understood as a
 commentary on this drama, producing dadaist mammals, extra ears, pigs
 with wings, activist crops, and 'fuzzy biological sabotage' [2].

 Biophilosophy implies a critique of all anthropomorphic conceptions
 of life. But is it possible to think this nonanthropomorphic life?
 Are we determined to yet again supplant a new term ('multiplicity')
 for an old one ('pattern')? The problem is not simply a nominalist
 one, not simply a game of logic; the problem is the very relation
 between 'life' and 'thought' (both Canguilhem and Foucault note that
 the most accurate concept of life would be life itself).
 Biophilosophy is an approach to nonhuman life, nonorganic life,
 anonymous life, indefinite life -- what Deleuze calls 'a life.' But
 the trick is to undo conventional biological thinking from within.
 Biophilosophy focuses on those modes of biological life that
 simultaneously escape their being exclusively biological life:
 microbes, epidemics, endosymbiosis, parasitism, swarms, packs,
 flocks, a-life, genetic algorithms, biopathways, smart dust,
 smartmobs, netwars -- there is a whole bestiary that asks us to think
 the life-multiplicity relation.



 Life is X
 ---------

 The central question of the philosophy of biology has to do with an
 essence of life, a 'principle of life.' What is life? Life is X --
 whatever X happens to be, eidos, mechanism, life-force, selection,
 code. The concept of 'life itself' promoted by geneticists during the
 post-WWII era (the genetic 'coding problem') was a renewal of a
 concept articulated by Aristotle in _De anima_ as well as his
 'biological' treatises. The implication of the very concept of 'life
 itself' is that 'life' is One. Whatever it is, life is one thing,
 essentially one thing, for otherwise we could not say 'Life is X.'
 Even when life reveals its contradictory nature, that contradiction
 is the ineffable key to life. An example is animal motility.
 Aristotle posed the question 'what makes the animal go?'; that is,
 from where does its energy come? The problem was picked up by
 the application of thermodynamics to animal physiology, with talk of
 animal 'electricity' and 'irritability' and 'vital forces.' Soon
 there was an ineffable 'life force' coursing through the animal,
 enabling it to counter the laws of thermodynamics.

 Today a similar process is happening with studies in
 self-organization and emergence. The question has changed, but its
 form of the problem is the same: 'how do simple local actions produce
 complex global patterns?' The effects of self-organization can be
 analyzed forever (e.g. 'ant colony optimization') and they can be
 applied to computer science (e.g. CG in film, telecommunications
 routing). But a central mysticism is produced at its core, for if
 there is no external, controlling factor (environment, genes,
 blueprints) then how can there be control at all? Again, 'life
 itself' the ineffable, the absent center. In this sense life follows
 the laws of thought: it is self-identical (whatever is living
 continues to be so until it ceases to be living), non-contradictory
 (something cannot both be living and non-living), and either is or is
 not (something either is or is not living, there is no grey zone to
 life). It is in this sense that 'life' and 'thought' find their
 common meeting point. Biophilosophy implies a critique of the
 dialectics of 'life itself.' It abandons the concept of 'life itself'
 that is forever caught between the poles of nature and culture,
 biology and technology, human and machine. Instead it develops
 concepts that always cut across and that form networks: the
 molecular, multiplicity, becoming-animal, life-resistance...But the
 point is not to simply repeat deleuzianisms, but rather to invent or
 diverge: the autonomy of affect, germinal life, wetwares, prevital
 transductions, organismic soft control, abstract sex, molecular
 invasions, geophilosophy, and what Deleuze calls 'the
 mathematico-biological systems of differenc/tiation' [3].



 Being, Time, Number
 -------------------

 The philosophy of biology is an epistemological endeavor, while
 biophilosophy is an ontological one. The philosophy of biology asks
 'which category?', while biophilosophy asks 'affected or affecting?'
 Biophilosophy ceaselessly spins out ontologies, none of them final,
 none of them lasting. An example: perhaps what Heidegger pointed to
 as the defining philosophical concern of modernity -- Being or
 ~dasein~ -- has permutated into one of the guiding concerns of the
 new millennium -- the problematic of 'life itself' or the ~zoe/bios~
 distinction. We are no longer worried about the grand metaphysical
 concerns of Being, Time, and the One. Biophilosophy is a permutation
 and transmutation of these concerns: not Being but the problematic of
 'life itself', a concern that asks us to rethink the concept of the
 vital and vitalism. Similarly, the concern with Time has become an
 interest in variation, transformation, change -- difference and
 repetition (the repetition of the different and the difference of
 each repetition). The contemporary interest in the event, becoming,
 and the virtual-actual pair are further variations of this. Finally,
 the imperative of the One -- that Being is One, that Time is One,
 that the subject is singular, that identity is the identification of
 the One, even the strange sameness of the Other in ethical thought --
 all of this asks us to pose the question: what would we have to do to
 the concept of 'number' to think beyond the One-many dichotomy? This
 is the question posed by Deleuze's _Difference and Repetition_, but
 it is already there in Plato's _Parmenides_. Hair, mud and dirt. Is
 there a concept of multiplicity that moves beyond the One-many? Could
 such a concept resist a simple denunciation of 'number' (quantity vs.
 quality, extensity vs. intensity, explication vs. implication). If
 there is a concept of number that runs throughout multiplicity (a
 proliferative, pervasive number), and if multiplicity is related to
 life, is there a living number -- a ~vitalist matheme~ -- that would
 move out of the philosophy of biology's trinity of soul-meat-pattern?
 Instead of what Badiou calls the split between the quantitative and
 qualitative, the closed and the open, 'number and animal,' is there
 an animal number? Being, Time, and the One thus get recombined as
 'life itself,' becoming, and number, which in turn ask us to consider
 or reconsider vitalism, the virtual, and multiplicity.



 Other-than-life
 ---------------

 The philosophy of biology poses the question, 'what is life?' In
 doing so, however, it rarely asks the inverse question, 'what is
 not-life?' Certainly death is not-life. But so is the rock, the
 chair, the clouds. What about the computer, lunch, or a nation-state,
 are they not-life as well? What about a doll? Memories? There is a
 whole negative classification of not-life implied in the positive
 question 'what is life?' Better yet, rather than the question of what
 is not-life, we can pose the question of the life that becomes
 not-life, an other-than-life, a becoming-nonliving. Four, preliminary
 examples:

  1. Swarm intelligence: 'Swarm intelligence' is a term currently
     used to describe an interdisciplinary research field that
     combines the biological studies of 'social insects' with
     computer science (especially software algorithms and multi-agent
     systems) [4]. Just as a group of insects that are individually
     'dumb' are able to collectively self-organize and forage for a
     food source or build a nest, so can simple software programs or
     robots self-organize in groups and carry out complex tasks. This
     local actions-global patterns approach is said to display
     'intelligent' or purposeful behavior at the global level. But we
     can also question and repurpose the term 'swarm intelligence,'
     for the tendency in this thinking is to always search for a
     higher-level unity which would be the guarantee of organization
     and order. Call it a 'superorganism' or a 'hive mind,' the
     implication is that purposeful activity can only occur through a
     process of meta-individualizing all group phenomena, subjecting
     the many-as-many to a renewed concept of the One. Action must
     come after individuation, not vice-versa. However the unique
     thing about insect swarms and other animal groups (packs,
     flocks, schools) is not just that there is no leader, but that
     there is something akin to a fully distributed control. Thus the
     political paradox of insect societies -- how to understand this
     balance between control and emergence, sovereignty and
     multiplicity? And thus the paradoxical question of the field of
     swarm intelligence -- can it be coded? Can one in fact engineer
     distributed control? Or are we stuck at the level of passive
     observers, limited in our ability to identify swarm
     intelligence, but helpless to enact it? What would have to be
     done to the concept of action in order to make of swarm
     intelligence a political concept? If there is a swarm
     intelligence, the 'intelligence' would surely have to be a
     frustratingly anonymous, nonanthropomorphic intelligence, the
     intelligence of 'a life.'

  2. Headless animality: The philosophy of biology is not only
     concerned with the unity of life ('Life is X'), but it ties this
     unity to the individual organism. Whether in natural history's
     classifications, Darwinian speciation, or the study of genomes,
     biology always begins from the individual. The individual is the
     starting point, the basic unit of study. Throughout all these
     levels, the organism has remained central. Organisms not only
     form species, but they are also formed by molecules and cells;
     organisms are the ideal point of mediation between the
     microscopic and macroscopic views of life. Thus it is no
     surprise to find philosophy raising the human above the animal
     based on the comparison of individual organisms. Aristotle,
     Descartes, Hobbes, Locke, Rousseau: the individual organism is
     the most basic unit through which the human is raised above the
     animal, the beast, the savage. This is especially the case when
     groups are concerned. Here insects are the privileged case
     study, perhaps the paradigmatic case of the not-human. Indeed,
     political thought has often contrasted the human and the insect
     precisely on this point. Hobbes notes that while both we and
     insects are 'social,' only we can lay down rights to establish a
     sovereign; Marx notes that insects also produce and build, but
     humans are able to abstract and plan before building. Thus even
     groups are individuals. Groups are composed of individuals that
     pre-exist them, and groups themselves form meta-individuals
     ('species,' 'races'). But there are also extrinsic group
     animals, the multiplicity-animals of packs, flocks, swarms. Yes,
     swarms can be understood to be composed of individual insects.
     But what if swarms, packs, and so on are actually inversions of
     the organism? What if they are instances in which the many
     pre-exist the One? An army ant swarm does have a morphogenetic
     aspect to it: there is a swarm front, a bivouac, and branching
     paths. But swarms, packs, flocks, schools are also defined
     precisely by their shapelessness and formlessness. They have no
     'head' let alone a 'face.' They are headless animals, acephalous
     animality. They are animality without head or tail, polysensory,
     poly-affective, 'amorphous but coordinated' [5].

  3. Molecular molecules: To begin with, we can suggest that
     molecules are not 'molecular.' As non-sensical as this sounds,
     it is important to understand the molecule as one in a whole
     series of units of composition and analysis: the organism, the
     organ, the tissue, the cell, the molecule. Each science of life
     is not just a noun (anatomy, biology) but also a verb
     ('anatomizing,' 'biologizing') in which the living is both
     analyzed and built up. What is the smallest unit of composition?
     This is also the first unit of analysis. Building up, breaking
     down. The process of individuation is central to thinking about
     life, whether it be about the 'building blocks of life' or the
     'code of life.' There are always 'powers of ten' in biology, a
     huge, ontological microscope that stratifies individuals (the
     'DNA makes RNA makes proteins, and proteins make us' mantra of
     molecular genetics). But what if all this has nothing to do with
     scale, or with strata, or with layering? There is a whole
     forgotten history of molecular biology which de-emphasizes the
     search for 'the' molecules (proteins or nucleic acids), and
     instead focuses on the relationality of molecules, their network
     dynamics, their temporal existence on the 'edge of chaos'
     (biocomplexity). On the one hand biology tells us that molecules
     build up and break down (some proteins break down molecules,
     others build up). But on the other hand a cursory look at
     microbes shows us the radical horizontality of molecules:
     symbiotic bacteria, contagious viruses, and horizontal gene
     transfer between microbes. An epidemic is molecular, but it is
     also social, technological, economic, political. Networks of
     infection, yes, but also networks of contagion, transportation,
     vaccination, quarantine, surveillance. This compression of
     networks, this topological intensification, is not the result of
     molecules, but is 'molecular.' A microbial life that has nothing
     to do with scale (micro- vs. macro-), but that is at once local
     and global. Even the common biological processes of gene
     expression, cell metabolism, and membrane signaling routinely
     create linkages and relations (microbe-animal-human), or rather
     they produce univocity-through-assemblages.

  4. Lifelike death: We speak excitedly about the ways that new
     technologies are 'life-like,' meaning the way that technology --
     something devoid of life -- is able to display characteristics
     or behaviors that for us approximate life. But it is never clear
     if the lifelike is a category of representation (the lifelike
     quality of the 'oval portrait'), performance ('never mind the
     man behind the curtain'), or simulation ('what is real, Neo?').
     Our own obsession is to constantly desire and yet worry about
     the lifelike: we want our phones to speak to us, but only if
     they say the right things. In popular culture, science fiction
     repeatedly plays out these scenarios where we produce a
     technical life in our own image, a fusion of technology and life
     in which the human constantly reproduces itself. Perhaps another
     approach to the lifelike is not to do with life or technology at
     all, but the lifelikeness of death. There is, in fact, a whole
     demonology of the lifelike to be considered. In popular culture,
     genre horror gives us many examples of lifelike death: zombies
     (the living dead), vampires (the undead), the phantasm (the
     disembodied spirit), and the demon (the possessed life). This is
     the lifelikeness of life passing away, going beyond itself,
     exiting itself. It is no mistake that these figures of lifelike
     death are often inhabited by fearfully ambivalent agents:
     viruses infecting the living dead, the 'bad blood' of the
     vampire, the phantasm enslaved my memory, and the demonic
     tearing of soul from body. Lifelike death is not the celebratory
     lifelikeness of our intelligent machines, but the ambivalent
     attitude towards a life that should not be living, an unholy
     life. This lifelike death is aporetic life: the dead that walk,
     the immortal being that is also the basest animals (bats, rats),
     the materialized spirit, the familiar face distorted beyond
     recognition. Perhaps there is a technoscientific side to this
     after all. For, wouldn't the limit-case of lifelike death be the
     point at which the organic can no longer be distinguished from
     the inorganic, the material from the immaterial? This is the
     domain of nanotechnology, the idea of inorganic life,
     programmable matter, an undiscovered 'occult media.'



 Ancient Life (or, the Biology of Cthulhu)
 -----------------------------------------

 'Biophilosophy for the 21st century' is an ambiguous statement.
 Biophilosophy does not begin with information networks,
 biotechnologies, nanotechnologies, or intelligent software. In a
 sense, Presocratic thinking is biophilosophical thinking. Heraclitus
 refers to a nonorganic life in this three examples of fire
 (formlessness in identity), flows (stepping into the river), and the
 body (stability through growth and decay). A common ~logos~ to all
 change. His opposite -- but in many ways his compliment -- is
 Parmenides, whose concept of the All-One attempts to comprehend
 multiplicity as another form of univocity. And then there are the
 Greek atomists, particles infinitely dense and mobile...

 Immediately a dissenting point is raised: 'are we not being reductive
 in our concept of life, as if life were only biological life, and not
 social, cultural, economic, religious and political life as well?'
 Indeed, isn't the problem the way in which biological and biomedical
 life has come to be the foundation of our emerging 'biopolitical'
 regimes? This 'bare life' serves as the alpha and the omega of social
 and political life, at once safeguarding the security of 'the
 population' while also producing a state of exception, a state of
 emergency, in which 'bare life' is both under attack and the object
 of preemptive strikes. Undoubtedly. Except that this cordons off our
 ability to think about life within the chess-match between
 disciplines. To the scientist who says 'life is genetic code' there
 is the sociologist who says 'life is the discriminatory
 implementation of genetics.' To the physicist who says 'life is the
 self-organization of matter and energy' the political scientist says
 'life is the struggle between human groups to instrumentalize natural
 resources.' To the humanities professor who says 'life is the set of
 metaphors we forget are metaphors,' there is the engineer who designs
 'programmable matter' and 'smart dust.' Once in a while, there are
 synergistic couplings, noisesome crosstalk that produces monsters: in
 the 1980s there was talk of chaos, in the 1990s talk of complexity,
 and crossing the millennium talk of networks. Or so the story goes.
 Perhaps we would like to do away with disciplines; and yet, for all
 the talk of 'third cultures' we still find the two cultures in the
 most banal, everyday instances.

 This not a manifesto. All the same, there are a number of
 misconceptions to address concerning biophilosophy. Biophilosophy is
 not a naive embrace of 'life,' a belief in the altruistic holism of
 all life on the planet. It is, however, a rigorous questioning of the
 twofold method of the philosophy of biology (principle of life,
 boundaries of articulation), and the divisions that are produced from
 this. Biophilosophy always asks, 'what relations are precluded in
 such-and-such a division, in such-and-such a classification?'
 Biophilosophy is not and should not be simply another name for
 self-organization, emergence, or complexity. While there is a fertile
 exchange between philosophy and biology on this point, it is clear
 that the sciences of complexity are unable to think both
 ontologically and politically as well. More often than not, they
 create a new portrait of nature (a nonlinear, metastable, complex
 nature), or worse, they subsume all non-natural elements under this
 new nature (thus free markets and/or 'democracy' are self-organizing
 and therefore inevitable). Not everything comes under the domain of
 biophilosophy, but at the same time one of biophilosophy's major
 concerns is the supposed foundationalism of biology and the
 biological-biomedical definitions of life. Biophilosophy is not
 simply a new vitalism, arguing for the ineffability and
 irreducibility of life's description. Yet this is perhaps the most
 frustrating and ambivalent aspect of biophilosophy. Biophilosophy is
 an attempt to draw out a political ontology, and yet it is also
 politically agonistic, even apathetic. There is no ~ressentiment~ in
 biophilosophy; only a commitment to a 'vital politics' accompanied by
 this 'molecular-wide' perspective. Biophilosophy picks up and
 reinvigorates the ontological questions left behind by the philosophy
 of biology. Why 'life'?



 Notes:
 ------

 [1] See my article 'Networks, Swarms, Multitudes' in _CTHEORY_
 (2004): part one (http://www.ctheory.net/text_file.asp?pick=422) and
 part two (http://www.ctheory.net/text_file.asp?pick=423).

 [2] In particular, see the work of SymbioticA
 (http://www.symbiotica.uwa.edu.au), a group of artists and scientists
 engaged in exploring cell and tissue culturing techniques as artistic
 practice. In a different vein, Critical Art Ensemble
 (http://www.critical-art.net) has, for some years, explored the
 relationships between activism, art, and biotechnology.

 [3] Aside from _A Thousand Plateaus_, see Deleuze's comments on life
 as 'resistance' in _Foucault_. Sean Hand, trans. London: Continuum,
 1999. For a sampling of other divergings from life, see Keith Ansell
 Pearson, _ Germinal Life_, New York: Routledge, 1999; Alain Badiou,
 "Of Life as a Name of Being, or Deleuze's Vitalist Ontology," _Pli:
 The Warwick Journal of Philosophy_ 10, 2000, 174-91; Mark Bonta and
 John Protevi, _Deleuze and Geophilosophy: A Guide and Glossary_,
 Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2004; Critical Art Ensemble,
 _The Molecular Invasion_, Brooklyn: Autonomedia, 2002; Manuel
 Delanda, "Immanence and Transcendence in the Genesis of Form," _South
 Atlantic Quarterly_ 96.3, Summer 1997: 499-514; Richard Doyle,
 _Wetwares: Experiments in Postvital Living_, Minneapolis: University
 of Minnesota Press, 2004; Miriam Fraser, Sarah Kember, and Celia
 Lury, "Inventive Life: Approaches to the New Vitalism," _Theory,
 Culture & Society_ 22.1, 2005, 1-14; Mark Hansen, "Becoming as
 Creative Involution?: Contextualizing Deleuze and Guattari's
 Biophilosophy," _Postmodern Culture_ 11.1, 2000; Adrian Mackenzie,
 "Bringing Sequences to Life: How Bioinformatics Corporealizes
 Sequence Data," _New Genetics and Society_ 22.3 (2003): 315-32;
 Lucianna Parisi, Abstract Sex: Philosophy, Bio-technology and the
 Mutations of Desire_, London: Continuum, 2004; Luciana Parisi and
 Tiziana Terranova, "Heat-Death: Emergence and Control in Genetic
 Engineering and Artificial Life," _CTHEORY_, 2000:
 http://www.ctheory.net/text_file.asp?pick=127; Eugene Thacker,
 _Biomedia_, Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 2004.

 [4] For a quick overview, see Eric Bonabeau and Guy Theraulaz, "Swarm
 Smarts," _Scientific American_ (March 2000): 72-79. For a more
 thorough, and more technical introduction, see Bonabeau and
 Theraulaz, _Swarm Intelligence: From Natural to Artificial Systems_,
 Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1999.

 [5] This is the phrase often used by John Arquilla and David Ronfeldt
 in their book on military swarming, _Swarming and the Future of
 Conflict_, Santa Monica: RAND, 2000.



 --------------------------------------------------------------------

 Eugene Thacker is Assistant Professor in the School of Literature,
 Communication, and Culture at Georgia Institute of Technology. He is
 the author of _Biomedia_ and _The Global Genome: Biotechnology,
 Politics, and Culture_.

 _____________________________________________________________________

 *
 * CTHEORY is an international journal of theory, technology and
 *    culture. Articles, interviews, and key book reviews in
 *    contemporary discourse are published weekly as well as
 *    theorisations of major "event-scenes" in the mediascape.
 *
 * Editors: Arthur and Marilouise Kroker
 *
 * Editorial Board: Jean Baudrillard (Paris), Paul Virilio (Paris),
 *   Bruce Sterling (Austin), R.U. Sirius (San Francisco), Siegfried
 *   Zielinski (Koeln), Stelarc (Melbourne), Richard Kadrey (San
 *   Francisco), DJ Spooky [Paul D. Miller] (NYC), Timothy Murray
 *   (Ithaca/Cornell), Lynn Hershman Leeson (San Francisco), Stephen
 *   Pfohl (Boston), Andrew Ross (NYC), David Cook (Toronto), Ralph
 *   Melcher (Sante Fe), Shannon Bell (Toronto), Gad Horowitz
 *   (Toronto), Andrew Wernick (Peterborough).
 *
 * In Memory: Kathy Acker
 *
 * Editorial Correspondents: Ken Hollings (UK),
 *   Maurice Charland (Canada) Steve Gibson (Canada/Sweden).
 *
 * Editorial Assistant: Ted Hiebert
 * WWW Design & Technical Advisor: Spencer Saunders (CTHEORY.NET)
 * WWW Engineer Emeritus: Carl Steadman

 _____________________________________________________________________

                To view CTHEORY online please visit:
                      http://www.ctheory.net/

            To view CTHEORY MULTIMEDIA online please visit:
                 http://ctheorymultimedia.cornell.edu/

 _____________________________________________________________________

 * CTHEORY includes:
 *
 * 1. Electronic reviews of key books in contemporary theory.
 *
 * 2. Electronic articles on theory, technology and culture.
 *
 * 3. Event-scenes in politics, culture and the mediascape.
 *
 * 4. Interviews with significant theorists, artists, and writers.
 *
 * 5. Multimedia theme issues and projects.
 *
 *
 * The Editors would like the thank the University of Victoria for
 *   financial and intellectual support of CTheory. In particular, the
 *   Editors would like to thank the Dean of Social Sciences, Dr. C.
 *   Peter Keller, the Dean of Engineering, Dr. D. Michael Miller and
 *   Dr. Jon Muzio, Department of Computer Science.
 *
 *
 * (C) Copyright Information:
 *
 *   All articles published in this journal are protected by
 *   copyright, which covers the exclusive rights to reproduce and
 *   distribute the article.  No material published in this journal
 *   may be translated, reproduced, photographed or stored on
 *   microfilm, in electronic databases, video disks, etc., without
 *   first obtaining written permission from CTheory.
 *   Email [log in to unmask] for more information.
 *
 *
 * Mailing address: CTHEORY, University of Victoria, PO Box 3050,
 *   Victoria, BC, Canada, V8W 3P5.
 *
 * Full text and microform versions are available from UMI, Ann Arbor,
 *   Michigan; and Canadian Periodical Index/Gale Canada, Toronto.
 *
 * Indexed in: International Political Science Abstracts/
 *   Documentation politique international; Sociological Abstract
 *   Inc.; Advance Bibliography of Contents: Political Science and
 *   Government; Canadian Periodical Index; Film and Literature Index.
 *
 _____________________________________________________________________

_______________________________________________
ctheory mailing list
[log in to unmask]
http://lists.uvic.ca/mailman/listinfo/ctheory

-- 
This message has been scanned for viruses and dangerous
content by the NorMAN MailScanner Service and is believed
to be clean.

The NorMAN MailScanner Service is operated by Information
Systems and Services, University of Newcastle upon Tyne.


====
This e-mail is intended solely for the addressee. It may contain private and
confidential information. If you are not the intended addressee, please take
no action based on it nor show a copy to anyone. Please reply to this e-mail
to highlight the error. You should also be aware that all electronic mail
from, to, or within Northumbria University may be the subject of a request
under the Freedom of Information Act 2000 and related legislation, and
therefore may be required to be disclosed to third parties.
This e-mail and attachments have been scanned for viruses prior to leaving
Northumbria University. Northumbria University will not be liable for any
losses as a result of any viruses being passed on.

************************************************************************************
Distributed through Cyber-Society-Live [CSL]: CSL is a moderated discussion
list made up of people who are interested in the interdisciplinary academic
study of Cyber Society in all its manifestations.To join the list please visit:
http://www.jiscmail.ac.uk/lists/cyber-society-live.html
*************************************************************************************

Top of Message | Previous Page | Permalink

JiscMail Tools


RSS Feeds and Sharing


Advanced Options


Archives

May 2024
April 2024
March 2024
February 2024
January 2024
December 2023
November 2023
October 2023
September 2023
August 2023
July 2023
June 2023
May 2023
April 2023
March 2023
February 2023
January 2023
December 2022
November 2022
October 2022
September 2022
August 2022
June 2022
May 2022
March 2022
February 2022
October 2021
July 2021
June 2021
April 2021
March 2021
February 2021
January 2021
December 2020
November 2020
October 2020
September 2020
July 2020
June 2020
May 2020
April 2020
February 2020
January 2020
December 2019
November 2019
October 2019
September 2019
August 2019
July 2019
June 2019
May 2019
March 2019
February 2019
January 2019
December 2018
November 2018
October 2018
September 2018
August 2018
July 2018
June 2018
May 2018
April 2018
March 2018
February 2018
January 2018
December 2017
November 2017
October 2017
September 2017
August 2017
July 2017
June 2017
May 2017
April 2017
March 2017
January 2017
December 2016
November 2016
October 2016
September 2016
August 2016
June 2016
May 2016
April 2016
March 2016
February 2016
January 2016
December 2015
November 2015
October 2015
September 2015
August 2015
July 2015
June 2015
May 2015
April 2015
March 2015
February 2015
January 2015
December 2014
November 2014
October 2014
September 2014
August 2014
June 2014
May 2014
April 2014
March 2014
February 2014
January 2014
December 2013
November 2013
October 2013
September 2013
August 2013
July 2013
June 2013
May 2013
April 2013
March 2013
February 2013
January 2013
December 2012
November 2012
October 2012
September 2012
August 2012
July 2012
June 2012
May 2012
April 2012
March 2012
February 2012
January 2012
December 2011
November 2011
October 2011
September 2011
July 2011
June 2011
May 2011
April 2011
March 2011
February 2011
January 2011
December 2010
November 2010
October 2010
September 2010
August 2010
July 2010
June 2010
May 2010
April 2010
March 2010
February 2010
January 2010
December 2009
November 2009
October 2009
September 2009
July 2009
June 2009
May 2009
April 2009
March 2009
February 2009
January 2009
December 2008
November 2008
October 2008
September 2008
June 2008
May 2008
April 2008
March 2008
February 2008
January 2008
December 2007
November 2007
October 2007
September 2007
June 2007
May 2007
April 2007
March 2007
February 2007
January 2007
2006
2005
2004
2003
2002
2001
2000


JiscMail is a Jisc service.

View our service policies at https://www.jiscmail.ac.uk/policyandsecurity/ and Jisc's privacy policy at https://www.jisc.ac.uk/website/privacy-notice

For help and support help@jisc.ac.uk

Secured by F-Secure Anti-Virus CataList Email List Search Powered by the LISTSERV Email List Manager